HomeHome Metamath Proof Explorer
Theorem List (p. 25 of 450)
< Previous  Next >
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version.

Mirrors  >  Metamath Home Page  >  MPE Home Page  >  Theorem List Contents  >  Recent Proofs       This page: Page List

Color key:    Metamath Proof Explorer  Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-28695)
  Hilbert Space Explorer  Hilbert Space Explorer
(28696-30218)
  Users' Mathboxes  Users' Mathboxes
(30219-44955)
 

Theorem List for Metamath Proof Explorer - 2401-2500   *Has distinct variable group(s)
TypeLabelDescription
Statement
 
Theoremax6e 2401 At least one individual exists. This is not a theorem of free logic, which is sound in empty domains. For such a logic, we would add this theorem as an axiom of set theory (Axiom 0 of [Kunen] p. 10). In the system consisting of ax-4 1810 through ax-9 2124, all axioms other than ax-6 1970 are believed to be theorems of free logic, although the system without ax-6 1970 is not complete in free logic.

Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. It is preferred to use ax6ev 1972 when it is sufficient. (Contributed by NM, 14-May-1993.) Shortened after ax13lem1 2392 became available. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 8-Sep-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)

𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦
 
Theoremax6 2402 Theorem showing that ax-6 1970 follows from the weaker version ax6v 1971. (Even though this theorem depends on ax-6 1970, all references of ax-6 1970 are made via ax6v 1971. An earlier version stated ax6v 1971 as a separate axiom, but having two axioms caused some confusion.)

This theorem should be referenced in place of ax-6 1970 so that all proofs can be traced back to ax6v 1971. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. When possible, use the weaker ax6v 1971 rather than ax6 2402 since the ax6v 1971 derivation is much shorter and requires fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 12-Nov-2013.) (Revised by NM, 25-Jul-2015.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 4-Feb-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)

¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦
 
Theoremaxc10 2403 Show that the original axiom ax-c10 36037 can be derived from ax6 2402 and axc7 2336 (on top of propositional calculus, ax-gen 1796, and ax-4 1810). See ax6fromc10 36047 for the rederivation of ax6 2402 from ax-c10 36037.

Normally, axc10 2403 should be used rather than ax-c10 36037, except by theorems specifically studying the latter's properties. Usage of this theorem has been discouraged later on to avoid ax-13 2390 propagation. Check out bj-axc10v 34115 for a weaker version requiring less axioms. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)

(∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑥𝜑) → 𝜑)
 
Theoremspimt 2404 Closed theorem form of spim 2405. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jan-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 21-Mar-2023.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ∧ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))) → (∀𝑥𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremspim 2405 Specialization, using implicit substitution. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. The spim 2405 series of theorems requires that only one direction of the substitution hypothesis hold. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Check out spimw 1973 for a version requiring less axioms. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jan-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 18-Feb-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜓    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremspimed 2406 Deduction version of spime 2407. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker spimedv 2197 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 14-May-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 19-Feb-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜒 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (𝜒 → (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremspime 2407 Existential introduction, using implicit substitution. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Check out spimew 1974 for a weaker version requiring less axioms. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 6-Mar-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜑    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓)
 
Theoremspimv 2408* A version of spim 2405 with a distinct variable requirement instead of a bound-variable hypothesis. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. See spimfv 2241 and spimvw 2002 for versions requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 31-Jul-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥𝜑𝜓)
 
TheoremspimvALT 2409* Alternate proof of spimv 2408. Note that it requires only ax-1 6 through ax-5 1911 together with ax6e 2401. Currently, proofs derive from ax6v 1971, but if ax-6 1970 could be used instead, this proof would reduce axiom usage. (Contributed by NM, 31-Jul-1993.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2145. (Revised by BJ, 29-Nov-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremspimev 2410* Distinct-variable version of spime 2407. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker spimevw 2001 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jan-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓)
 
Theoremspv 2411* Specialization, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker spvv 2003 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremspei 2412 Inference from existential specialization, using implicit substitution. Remove a distinct variable constraint. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker speiv 1976 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 19-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   𝜓       𝑥𝜑
 
Theoremchvar 2413 Implicit substitution of 𝑦 for 𝑥 into a theorem. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker chvarfv 2242 if possible. (Contributed by Raph Levien, 9-Jul-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜓    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   𝜑       𝜓
 
Theoremchvarv 2414* Implicit substitution of 𝑦 for 𝑥 into a theorem. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker chvarvv 2005 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 20-Apr-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 22-Apr-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   𝜑       𝜓
 
Theoremcbv3 2415 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution, that does not use ax-c9 36041. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker cbv3v 2355 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑦𝜑    &   𝑥𝜓    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜓)
 
Theoremcbval 2416 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Check out cbvalw 2042, cbvalvw 2043, cbvalv1 2361 for versions requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 13-May-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑦𝜑    &   𝑥𝜓    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜓)
 
Theoremcbvex 2417 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Check out cbvexvw 2044, cbvexv1 2362 for weaker versions requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑦𝜑    &   𝑥𝜓    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑦𝜓)
 
Theoremcbvalv 2418* Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. See cbvalvw 2043 for a version requiring fewer axioms, to be preferred when sufficient. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2145, shorten. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 11-Sep-2023.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜓)
 
Theoremcbvexv 2419* Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. See cbvexvw 2044 for a version requiring fewer axioms, to be preferred when sufficient. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2145, shorten. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 11-Sep-2023.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑦𝜓)
 
TheoremcbvalvOLD 2420* Obsolete version of cbvalv 2418 as of 11-Sep-2023. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2145. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 17-Jul-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜓)
 
TheoremcbvexvOLD 2421* Obsolete version of cbvexv 2419 as of 11-Sep-2023. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2145. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 17-Jul-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑦𝜓)
 
Theoremcbv1 2422 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. See cbv1v 2356 with disjoint variable conditions, not depending on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) Format hypotheses to common style. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑦𝜑    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑦𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒)    &   (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒)))       (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∀𝑦𝜒))
 
Theoremcbv2 2423 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. See cbv2w 2357 with disjoint variable conditions, not depending on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) Format hypotheses to common style, avoid ax-10 2145. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 10-Sep-2023.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑦𝜑    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑦𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒)    &   (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒)))       (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜒))
 
Theoremcbv3h 2424 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker cbv3hv 2360 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 8-Jun-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜑)    &   (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜓)
 
Theoremcbv1h 2425 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑦𝜓))    &   (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒))    &   (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒)))       (∀𝑥𝑦𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∀𝑦𝜒))
 
Theoremcbv2h 2426 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑦𝜓))    &   (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒))    &   (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒)))       (∀𝑥𝑦𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜒))
 
Theoremcbv2OLD 2427 Obsolete version of cbv2 2423 as of 10-Sep-2023. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) Format hypotheses to common style. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑦𝜑    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑦𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒)    &   (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒)))       (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜒))
 
Theoremcbvald 2428* Deduction used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution, particularly useful in conjunction with dvelim 2473. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. See cbvaldw 2358 for a version with 𝑥, 𝑦 disjoint, not depending on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑦𝜑    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑦𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒)))       (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜒))
 
Theoremcbvexd 2429* Deduction used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution, particularly useful in conjunction with dvelim 2473. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker cbvexdw 2359 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑦𝜑    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑦𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒)))       (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∃𝑦𝜒))
 
Theoremcbvaldva 2430* Rule used to change the bound variable in a universal quantifier with implicit substitution. Deduction form. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker cbvaldvaw 2045 if possible. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((𝜑𝑥 = 𝑦) → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜒))
 
Theoremcbvexdva 2431* Rule used to change the bound variable in an existential quantifier with implicit substitution. Deduction form. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker cbvexdvaw 2046 if possible. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((𝜑𝑥 = 𝑦) → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∃𝑦𝜒))
 
Theoremcbval2 2432* Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker cbval2v 2363 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 22-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-Sep-2023.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑧𝜑    &   𝑤𝜑    &   𝑥𝜓    &   𝑦𝜓    &   ((𝑥 = 𝑧𝑦 = 𝑤) → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥𝑦𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑧𝑤𝜓)
 
Theoremcbval2OLD 2433* Obsolete version of cbval2 2432 as of 11-Sep-2023. (Contributed by NM, 22-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 22-Apr-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
𝑧𝜑    &   𝑤𝜑    &   𝑥𝜓    &   𝑦𝜓    &   ((𝑥 = 𝑧𝑦 = 𝑤) → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥𝑦𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑧𝑤𝜓)
 
Theoremcbvex2 2434* Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker cbvex2v 2365 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 16-Jun-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑧𝜑    &   𝑤𝜑    &   𝑥𝜓    &   𝑦𝜓    &   ((𝑥 = 𝑧𝑦 = 𝑤) → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃𝑥𝑦𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑧𝑤𝜓)
 
Theoremcbval2vv 2435* Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker cbval2vw 2047 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 4-Feb-2005.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2145. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 18-Jul-2021.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((𝑥 = 𝑧𝑦 = 𝑤) → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥𝑦𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑧𝑤𝜓)
 
Theoremcbvex2vv 2436* Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker cbvex2vw 2048 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 26-Jul-1995.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2145. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 18-Jul-2021.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((𝑥 = 𝑧𝑦 = 𝑤) → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃𝑥𝑦𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑧𝑤𝜓)
 
Theoremcbvex4v 2437* Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker cbvex4vw 2049 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 26-Jul-1995.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((𝑥 = 𝑣𝑦 = 𝑢) → (𝜑𝜓))    &   ((𝑧 = 𝑓𝑤 = 𝑔) → (𝜓𝜒))       (∃𝑥𝑦𝑧𝑤𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑣𝑢𝑓𝑔𝜒)
 
Theoremequs4 2438 Lemma used in proofs of implicit substitution properties. The converse requires either a disjoint variable condition (sb56 2277) or a non-freeness hypothesis (equs45f 2482). Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. See equs4v 2006 for a weaker version requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 10-May-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-May-2014.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 5-Feb-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) → ∃𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑))
 
Theoremequsal 2439 An equivalence related to implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. See equsalvw 2010 and equsalv 2268 for versions with disjoint variable conditions proved from fewer axioms. See also the dual form equsex 2440. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jun-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 5-Feb-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜓    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)
 
Theoremequsex 2440 An equivalence related to implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. See equsexvw 2011 and equsexv 2269 for versions with disjoint variable conditions proved from fewer axioms. See also the dual form equsal 2439. See equsexALT 2441 for an alternate proof. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 6-Feb-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜓    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)
 
TheoremequsexALT 2441 Alternate proof of equsex 2440. This proves the result directly, instead of as a corollary of equsal 2439 via equs4 2438. Note in particular that only existential quantifiers appear in the proof and that the only step requiring ax-13 2390 is ax6e 2401. This proof mimics that of equsal 2439 (in particular, note that pm5.32i 577, exbii 1848, 19.41 2237, mpbiran 707 correspond respectively to pm5.74i 273, albii 1820, 19.23 2211, a1bi 365). (Contributed by BJ, 20-Aug-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜓    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)
 
Theoremequsalh 2442 An equivalence related to implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. See equsalhw 2299 for a version with a disjoint variable condition requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jun-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)
 
Theoremequsexh 2443 An equivalence related to implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. See equsexhv 2300 for a version with a disjoint variable condition which does not require ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)
 
Theoremaxc15 2444 Derivation of set.mm's original ax-c15 36040 from ax-c11n 36039 and the shorter ax-12 2177 that has replaced it.

Theorem ax12 2445 shows the reverse derivation of ax-12 2177 from ax-c15 36040.

Normally, axc15 2444 should be used rather than ax-c15 36040, except by theorems specifically studying the latter's properties. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 26-Mar-2023.) (New usage is discouraged.)

(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑))))
 
Theoremax12 2445 Rederivation of axiom ax-12 2177 from ax12v 2178 (used only via sp 2182) , axc11r 2386, and axc15 2444 (on top of Tarski's FOL). Since this version depends on ax-13 2390, usage of the weaker ax12v 2178, ax12w 2137, ax12i 1969 are preferred. (Contributed by NM, 22-Jan-2007.) Proof uses contemporary axioms. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 8-Aug-2020.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 4-Jul-2021.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)))
 
Theoremax12b 2446 A bidirectional version of axc15 2444. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦𝑥 = 𝑦) → (𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)))
 
Theoremax13ALT 2447 Alternate proof of ax13 2393 from FOL, sp 2182, and axc9 2400. (Contributed by NM, 21-Dec-2015.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 31-Jan-2018.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑦 = 𝑧 → ∀𝑥 𝑦 = 𝑧))
 
Theoremaxc11n 2448 Derive set.mm's original ax-c11n 36039 from others. Commutation law for identical variable specifiers. The antecedent and consequent are true when 𝑥 and 𝑦 are substituted with the same variable. Lemma L12 in [Megill] p. 445 (p. 12 of the preprint). If a disjoint variable condition is added on 𝑥 and 𝑦, then this becomes an instance of aevlem 2060. Use aecom 2449 instead when this does not lengthen the proof. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 10-May-1993.) (Revised by NM, 7-Nov-2015.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 6-Mar-2018.) (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 30-Nov-2019.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 29-Mar-2021.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jul-2021.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥)
 
Theoremaecom 2449 Commutation law for identical variable specifiers. Both sides of the biconditional are true when 𝑥 and 𝑦 are substituted with the same variable. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 10-May-1993.) Change to a biconditional. (Revised by BJ, 26-Sep-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 ↔ ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥)
 
Theoremaecoms 2450 A commutation rule for identical variable specifiers. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 10-May-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)       (∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremnaecoms 2451 A commutation rule for distinct variable specifiers. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)       (¬ ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremaxc11 2452 Show that ax-c11 36038 can be derived from ax-c11n 36039 in the form of axc11n 2448. Normally, axc11 2452 should be used rather than ax-c11 36038, except by theorems specifically studying the latter's properties. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker axc11v 2265 when possible. (Contributed by NM, 16-May-2008.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 21-Apr-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜑))
 
Theoremhbae 2453 All variables are effectively bound in an identical variable specifier. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker hbaev 2064 when possible. (Contributed by NM, 13-May-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 21-Apr-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦)
 
Theoremhbnae 2454 All variables are effectively bound in a distinct variable specifier. Lemma L19 in [Megill] p. 446 (p. 14 of the preprint). Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker hbnaev 2067 when possible. (Contributed by NM, 13-May-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 ¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦)
 
Theoremnfae 2455 All variables are effectively bound in an identical variable specifier. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑧𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦
 
Theoremnfnae 2456 All variables are effectively bound in a distinct variable specifier. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker nfnaew 2153 when possible. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑧 ¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦
 
Theoremhbnaes 2457 Rule that applies hbnae 2454 to antecedent. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 15-May-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑧 ¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)       (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)
 
Theoremaxc16i 2458* Inference with axc16 2262 as its conclusion. Usage of axc16 2262 is preferred since it requires fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 20-May-2008.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑧 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)       (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑))
 
Theoremaxc16nfALT 2459* Alternate proof of axc16nf 2264, shorter but requiring ax-11 2161 and ax-13 2390. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → Ⅎ𝑧𝜑)
 
Theoremdral2 2460 Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Usage of albidv 1921 is preferred, which requires fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.) Allow a shortening of dral1 2461. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 4-Mar-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑧𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑧𝜓))
 
Theoremdral1 2461 Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker dral1v 2387 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 24-Nov-1994.) Remove dependency on ax-11 2161. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 6-Sep-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜓))
 
Theoremdral1ALT 2462 Alternate proof of dral1 2461, shorter but requiring ax-11 2161. (Contributed by NM, 24-Nov-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 22-Apr-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜓))
 
Theoremdrex1 2463 Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker drex1v 2388 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∃𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑦𝜓))
 
Theoremdrex2 2464 Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Usage of exbidv 1922 is preferred, which requires fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∃𝑧𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑧𝜓))
 
Theoremdrnf1 2465 Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker drnf1v 2389 if possible. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ↔ Ⅎ𝑦𝜓))
 
Theoremdrnf2 2466 Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Usage of nfbidv 1923 is preferred, which requires fewer axioms. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 5-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (Ⅎ𝑧𝜑 ↔ Ⅎ𝑧𝜓))
 
Theoremnfald2 2467 Variation on nfald 2347 which adds the hypothesis that 𝑥 and 𝑦 are distinct in the inner subproof. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Check out nfald 2347 for a version requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 8-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑦𝜑    &   ((𝜑 ∧ ¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦) → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)       (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝑦𝜓)
 
Theoremnfexd2 2468 Variation on nfexd 2348 which adds the hypothesis that 𝑥 and 𝑦 are distinct in the inner subproof. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Check out nfexd 2348 for a version requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 8-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑦𝜑    &   ((𝜑 ∧ ¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦) → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)       (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝑦𝜓)
 
Theoremexdistrf 2469 Distribution of existential quantifiers, with a bound-variable hypothesis saying that 𝑦 is not free in 𝜑, but 𝑥 can be free in 𝜑 (and there is no distinct variable condition on 𝑥 and 𝑦). Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Check out exdistr 1955 for a version requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-Mar-2013.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 14-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → Ⅎ𝑦𝜑)       (∃𝑥𝑦(𝜑𝜓) → ∃𝑥(𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑦𝜓))
 
Theoremdvelimf 2470 Version of dvelimv 2474 without any variable restrictions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 1-Oct-2002.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑧𝜓    &   (𝑧 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)
 
Theoremdvelimdf 2471 Deduction form of dvelimf 2470. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 7-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑧𝜑    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑧𝜒)    &   (𝜑 → (𝑧 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒)))       (𝜑 → (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒))
 
Theoremdvelimh 2472 Version of dvelim 2473 without any variable restrictions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Check out dvelimhw 2366 for a version requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 1-Oct-2002.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜓 → ∀𝑧𝜓)    &   (𝑧 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremdvelim 2473* This theorem can be used to eliminate a distinct variable restriction on 𝑥 and 𝑧 and replace it with the "distinctor" ¬ ∀𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦 as an antecedent. 𝜑 normally has 𝑧 free and can be read 𝜑(𝑧), and 𝜓 substitutes 𝑦 for 𝑧 and can be read 𝜑(𝑦). We do not require that 𝑥 and 𝑦 be distinct: if they are not, the distinctor will become false (in multiple-element domains of discourse) and "protect" the consequent.

To obtain a closed-theorem form of this inference, prefix the hypotheses with 𝑥𝑧, conjoin them, and apply dvelimdf 2471.

Other variants of this theorem are dvelimh 2472 (with no distinct variable restrictions) and dvelimhw 2366 (that avoids ax-13 2390). Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Check out dvelimhw 2366 for a version requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 23-Nov-1994.) (New usage is discouraged.)

(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝑧 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremdvelimv 2474* Similar to dvelim 2473 with first hypothesis replaced by a distinct variable condition. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Check out dvelimhw 2366 for a version requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jul-2015.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 30-Apr-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑧 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremdvelimnf 2475* Version of dvelim 2473 using "not free" notation. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜑    &   (𝑧 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)
 
Theoremdveeq2ALT 2476* Alternate proof of dveeq2 2396, shorter but requiring ax-11 2161. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (Revised by NM, 20-Jul-2015.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑧 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑥 𝑧 = 𝑦))
 
Theoremequvini 2477 A variable introduction law for equality. Lemma 15 of [Monk2] p. 109, however we do not require 𝑧 to be distinct from 𝑥 and 𝑦. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. See equvinv 2036 for a shorter proof requiring fewer axioms when 𝑧 is required to be distinct from 𝑥 and 𝑦. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jan-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 16-Sep-2023.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∃𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑧𝑧 = 𝑦))
 
TheoremequviniOLD 2478 Obsolete version of equvini 2477 as of 16-Sep-2023. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jan-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 15-Sep-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∃𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑧𝑧 = 𝑦))
 
Theoremequvel 2479 A variable elimination law for equality with no distinct variable requirements. Compare equvini 2477. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use equvelv 2038 when possible. (Contributed by NM, 1-Mar-2013.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 17-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 15-Jun-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑧(𝑧 = 𝑥𝑧 = 𝑦) → 𝑥 = 𝑦)
 
Theoremequs5a 2480 A property related to substitution that unlike equs5 2483 does not require a distinctor antecedent. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. This proof uses ax12 2445, see equs5aALT 2384 for an alternative one using ax-12 2177 but not ax13 2393. Usage of the weaker equs5av 2279 is preferred, which uses ax12v2 2179, but not ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∃𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜑) → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑))
 
Theoremequs5e 2481 A property related to substitution that unlike equs5 2483 does not require a distinctor antecedent. This proof uses ax12 2445, see equs5eALT 2385 for an alternative one using ax-12 2177 but not ax13 2393. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 15-Jan-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∃𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∃𝑦𝜑))
 
Theoremequs45f 2482 Two ways of expressing substitution when 𝑦 is not free in 𝜑. The implication "to the left" is equs4 2438 and does not require the non-freeness hypothesis. Theorem sb56 2277 replaces the non-freeness hypothesis with a disjoint variable condition and equs5 2483 replaces it with a distinctor as antecedent. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑦𝜑       (∃𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) ↔ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑))
 
Theoremequs5 2483 Lemma used in proofs of substitution properties. If there is a disjoint variable condition on 𝑥, 𝑦, then sb56 2277 can be used instead; if 𝑦 is not free in 𝜑, then equs45f 2482 can be used. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 14-May-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 1-Oct-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∃𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) ↔ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)))
 
Theoremdveel1 2484* Quantifier introduction when one pair of variables is distinct. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑦𝑧 → ∀𝑥 𝑦𝑧))
 
Theoremdveel2 2485* Quantifier introduction when one pair of variables is distinct. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑧𝑦 → ∀𝑥 𝑧𝑦))
 
Theoremaxc14 2486 Axiom ax-c14 36042 is redundant if we assume ax-5 1911. Remark 9.6 in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint), regarding axiom scheme C14'.

Note that 𝑤 is a dummy variable introduced in the proof. Its purpose is to satisfy the distinct variable requirements of dveel2 2485 and ax-5 1911. By the end of the proof it has vanished, and the final theorem has no distinct variable requirements. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 29-Jun-1995.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)

(¬ ∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 → (¬ ∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 → (𝑥𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥𝑦)))
 
Theoremsb6x 2487 Equivalence involving substitution for a variable not free. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Usage of sb6 2093 is preferred, which requires fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jun-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑥𝜑       ([𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑))
 
Theoremsbequ5 2488 Substitution does not change an identical variable specifier. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 15-May-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
([𝑤 / 𝑧]∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 ↔ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦)
 
Theoremsbequ6 2489 Substitution does not change a distinctor. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
([𝑤 / 𝑧] ¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 ↔ ¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦)
 
Theoremsb5rf 2490 Reversed substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 20-Sep-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑦𝜑       (𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑦(𝑦 = 𝑥 ∧ [𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑))
 
Theoremsb6rf 2491 Reversed substitution. For a version requiring disjoint variables, but fewer axioms, see sb6rfv 2376. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. Use the weaker sb6rfv 2376 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 21-Sep-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑦𝜑       (𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦(𝑦 = 𝑥 → [𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑))
 
Theoremax12vALT 2492* Alternate proof of ax12v2 2179, shorter, but depending on more axioms. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)))
 
Theorem2ax6elem 2493 We can always find values matching 𝑥 and 𝑦, as long as they are represented by distinct variables. This theorem merges two ax6e 2401 instances 𝑧𝑧 = 𝑥 and 𝑤𝑤 = 𝑦 into a common expression. Alan Sare contributed a variant of this theorem with distinct variable conditions before, see ax6e2nd 40941. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 27-Sep-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(¬ ∀𝑤 𝑤 = 𝑧 → ∃𝑧𝑤(𝑧 = 𝑥𝑤 = 𝑦))
 
Theorem2ax6e 2494* We can always find values matching 𝑥 and 𝑦, as long as they are represented by distinct variables. Version of 2ax6elem 2493 with a distinct variable constraint. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 28-Sep-2018.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 3-Oct-2023.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑧𝑤(𝑧 = 𝑥𝑤 = 𝑦)
 
Theorem2ax6eOLD 2495* Obsolete version of 2ax6e 2494 as of 3-Oct-2023. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 28-Sep-2018.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑧𝑤(𝑧 = 𝑥𝑤 = 𝑦)
 
Theorem2sb5rf 2496* Reversed double substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) Remove distinct variable constraints. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 28-Sep-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑧𝜑    &   𝑤𝜑       (𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑧𝑤((𝑧 = 𝑥𝑤 = 𝑦) ∧ [𝑧 / 𝑥][𝑤 / 𝑦]𝜑))
 
Theorem2sb6rf 2497* Reversed double substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) Remove variable constraints. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 28-Sep-2018.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-Apr-2023.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑧𝜑    &   𝑤𝜑       (𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑧𝑤((𝑧 = 𝑥𝑤 = 𝑦) → [𝑧 / 𝑥][𝑤 / 𝑦]𝜑))
 
Theoremsbel2x 2498* Elimination of double substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 29-Sep-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑥𝑦((𝑥 = 𝑧𝑦 = 𝑤) ∧ [𝑦 / 𝑤][𝑥 / 𝑧]𝜑))
 
Theoremsb4b 2499 Simplified definition of substitution when variables are distinct. Version of sb6 2093 with a distinctor. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2390. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1997.) Revise df-sb 2070. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 21-Feb-2024.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑡 → ([𝑡 / 𝑥]𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑡𝜑)))
 
Theoremsb4bOLD 2500 Obsolete version of sb4b 2499 as of 21-Feb-2024. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1997.) Revise df-sb 2070. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 25-Jul-2023.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑡 → ([𝑡 / 𝑥]𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑡𝜑)))
    < Previous  Next >

Page List
Jump to page: Contents  1 1-100 2 101-200 3 201-300 4 301-400 5 401-500 6 501-600 7 601-700 8 701-800 9 801-900 10 901-1000 11 1001-1100 12 1101-1200 13 1201-1300 14 1301-1400 15 1401-1500 16 1501-1600 17 1601-1700 18 1701-1800 19 1801-1900 20 1901-2000 21 2001-2100 22 2101-2200 23 2201-2300 24 2301-2400 25 2401-2500 26 2501-2600 27 2601-2700 28 2701-2800 29 2801-2900 30 2901-3000 31 3001-3100 32 3101-3200 33 3201-3300 34 3301-3400 35 3401-3500 36 3501-3600 37 3601-3700 38 3701-3800 39 3801-3900 40 3901-4000 41 4001-4100 42 4101-4200 43 4201-4300 44 4301-4400 45 4401-4500 46 4501-4600 47 4601-4700 48 4701-4800 49 4801-4900 50 4901-5000 51 5001-5100 52 5101-5200 53 5201-5300 54 5301-5400 55 5401-5500 56 5501-5600 57 5601-5700 58 5701-5800 59 5801-5900 60 5901-6000 61 6001-6100 62 6101-6200 63 6201-6300 64 6301-6400 65 6401-6500 66 6501-6600 67 6601-6700 68 6701-6800 69 6801-6900 70 6901-7000 71 7001-7100 72 7101-7200 73 7201-7300 74 7301-7400 75 7401-7500 76 7501-7600 77 7601-7700 78 7701-7800 79 7801-7900 80 7901-8000 81 8001-8100 82 8101-8200 83 8201-8300 84 8301-8400 85 8401-8500 86 8501-8600 87 8601-8700 88 8701-8800 89 8801-8900 90 8901-9000 91 9001-9100 92 9101-9200 93 9201-9300 94 9301-9400 95 9401-9500 96 9501-9600 97 9601-9700 98 9701-9800 99 9801-9900 100 9901-10000 101 10001-10100 102 10101-10200 103 10201-10300 104 10301-10400 105 10401-10500 106 10501-10600 107 10601-10700 108 10701-10800 109 10801-10900 110 10901-11000 111 11001-11100 112 11101-11200 113 11201-11300 114 11301-11400 115 11401-11500 116 11501-11600 117 11601-11700 118 11701-11800 119 11801-11900 120 11901-12000 121 12001-12100 122 12101-12200 123 12201-12300 124 12301-12400 125 12401-12500 126 12501-12600 127 12601-12700 128 12701-12800 129 12801-12900 130 12901-13000 131 13001-13100 132 13101-13200 133 13201-13300 134 13301-13400 135 13401-13500 136 13501-13600 137 13601-13700 138 13701-13800 139 13801-13900 140 13901-14000 141 14001-14100 142 14101-14200 143 14201-14300 144 14301-14400 145 14401-14500 146 14501-14600 147 14601-14700 148 14701-14800 149 14801-14900 150 14901-15000 151 15001-15100 152 15101-15200 153 15201-15300 154 15301-15400 155 15401-15500 156 15501-15600 157 15601-15700 158 15701-15800 159 15801-15900 160 15901-16000 161 16001-16100 162 16101-16200 163 16201-16300 164 16301-16400 165 16401-16500 166 16501-16600 167 16601-16700 168 16701-16800 169 16801-16900 170 16901-17000 171 17001-17100 172 17101-17200 173 17201-17300 174 17301-17400 175 17401-17500 176 17501-17600 177 17601-17700 178 17701-17800 179 17801-17900 180 17901-18000 181 18001-18100 182 18101-18200 183 18201-18300 184 18301-18400 185 18401-18500 186 18501-18600 187 18601-18700 188 18701-18800 189 18801-18900 190 18901-19000 191 19001-19100 192 19101-19200 193 19201-19300 194 19301-19400 195 19401-19500 196 19501-19600 197 19601-19700 198 19701-19800 199 19801-19900 200 19901-20000 201 20001-20100 202 20101-20200 203 20201-20300 204 20301-20400 205 20401-20500 206 20501-20600 207 20601-20700 208 20701-20800 209 20801-20900 210 20901-21000 211 21001-21100 212 21101-21200 213 21201-21300 214 21301-21400 215 21401-21500 216 21501-21600 217 21601-21700 218 21701-21800 219 21801-21900 220 21901-22000 221 22001-22100 222 22101-22200 223 22201-22300 224 22301-22400 225 22401-22500 226 22501-22600 227 22601-22700 228 22701-22800 229 22801-22900 230 22901-23000 231 23001-23100 232 23101-23200 233 23201-23300 234 23301-23400 235 23401-23500 236 23501-23600 237 23601-23700 238 23701-23800 239 23801-23900 240 23901-24000 241 24001-24100 242 24101-24200 243 24201-24300 244 24301-24400 245 24401-24500 246 24501-24600 247 24601-24700 248 24701-24800 249 24801-24900 250 24901-25000 251 25001-25100 252 25101-25200 253 25201-25300 254 25301-25400 255 25401-25500 256 25501-25600 257 25601-25700 258 25701-25800 259 25801-25900 260 25901-26000 261 26001-26100 262 26101-26200 263 26201-26300 264 26301-26400 265 26401-26500 266 26501-26600 267 26601-26700 268 26701-26800 269 26801-26900 270 26901-27000 271 27001-27100 272 27101-27200 273 27201-27300 274 27301-27400 275 27401-27500 276 27501-27600 277 27601-27700 278 27701-27800 279 27801-27900 280 27901-28000 281 28001-28100 282 28101-28200 283 28201-28300 284 28301-28400 285 28401-28500 286 28501-28600 287 28601-28700 288 28701-28800 289 28801-28900 290 28901-29000 291 29001-29100 292 29101-29200 293 29201-29300 294 29301-29400 295 29401-29500 296 29501-29600 297 29601-29700 298 29701-29800 299 29801-29900 300 29901-30000 301 30001-30100 302 30101-30200 303 30201-30300 304 30301-30400 305 30401-30500 306 30501-30600 307 30601-30700 308 30701-30800 309 30801-30900 310 30901-31000 311 31001-31100 312 31101-31200 313 31201-31300 314 31301-31400 315 31401-31500 316 31501-31600 317 31601-31700 318 31701-31800 319 31801-31900 320 31901-32000 321 32001-32100 322 32101-32200 323 32201-32300 324 32301-32400 325 32401-32500 326 32501-32600 327 32601-32700 328 32701-32800 329 32801-32900 330 32901-33000 331 33001-33100 332 33101-33200 333 33201-33300 334 33301-33400 335 33401-33500 336 33501-33600 337 33601-33700 338 33701-33800 339 33801-33900 340 33901-34000 341 34001-34100 342 34101-34200 343 34201-34300 344 34301-34400 345 34401-34500 346 34501-34600 347 34601-34700 348 34701-34800 349 34801-34900 350 34901-35000 351 35001-35100 352 35101-35200 353 35201-35300 354 35301-35400 355 35401-35500 356 35501-35600 357 35601-35700 358 35701-35800 359 35801-35900 360 35901-36000 361 36001-36100 362 36101-36200 363 36201-36300 364 36301-36400 365 36401-36500 366 36501-36600 367 36601-36700 368 36701-36800 369 36801-36900 370 36901-37000 371 37001-37100 372 37101-37200 373 37201-37300 374 37301-37400 375 37401-37500 376 37501-37600 377 37601-37700 378 37701-37800 379 37801-37900 380 37901-38000 381 38001-38100 382 38101-38200 383 38201-38300 384 38301-38400 385 38401-38500 386 38501-38600 387 38601-38700 388 38701-38800 389 38801-38900 390 38901-39000 391 39001-39100 392 39101-39200 393 39201-39300 394 39301-39400 395 39401-39500 396 39501-39600 397 39601-39700 398 39701-39800 399 39801-39900 400 39901-40000 401 40001-40100 402 40101-40200 403 40201-40300 404 40301-40400 405 40401-40500 406 40501-40600 407 40601-40700 408 40701-40800 409 40801-40900 410 40901-41000 411 41001-41100 412 41101-41200 413 41201-41300 414 41301-41400 415 41401-41500 416 41501-41600 417 41601-41700 418 41701-41800 419 41801-41900 420 41901-42000 421 42001-42100 422 42101-42200 423 42201-42300 424 42301-42400 425 42401-42500 426 42501-42600 427 42601-42700 428 42701-42800 429 42801-42900 430 42901-43000 431 43001-43100 432 43101-43200 433 43201-43300 434 43301-43400 435 43401-43500 436 43501-43600 437 43601-43700 438 43701-43800 439 43801-43900 440 43901-44000 441 44001-44100 442 44101-44200 443 44201-44300 444 44301-44400 445 44401-44500 446 44501-44600 447 44601-44700 448 44701-44800 449 44801-44900 450 44901-44955
  Copyright terms: Public domain < Previous  Next >