Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 87 of 464) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29181) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29182-30704) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30705-46395) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | fsetdmprc0 8601* | The set of functions with a proper class as domain is empty. (Contributed by AV, 22-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∉ V → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓 Fn 𝐴} = ∅) | ||
Theorem | fsetex 8602* | The set of functions between two classes exists if the codomain exists. Generalization of mapex 8579 to arbitrary domains. (Contributed by AV, 14-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | f1setex 8603* | The set of injections between two classes exists if the codomain exists. (Contributed by AV, 14-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴–1-1→𝐵} ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | fosetex 8604* | The set of surjections between two classes exists (without any precondition). (Contributed by AV, 8-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴–onto→𝐵} ∈ V | ||
Theorem | f1osetex 8605* | The set of bijections between two classes exists. (Contributed by AV, 30-Mar-2024.) (Revised by AV, 8-Aug-2024.) (Proof shortened by SN, 22-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵} ∈ V | ||
Theorem | fsetfcdm 8606* | The class of functions with a given domain and a given codomain is mapped, through evaluation at a point of the domain, into the codomain. (Contributed by AV, 15-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} & ⊢ 𝑆 = (𝑔 ∈ 𝐹 ↦ (𝑔‘𝑋)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝑆:𝐹⟶𝐵) | ||
Theorem | fsetfocdm 8607* | The class of functions with a given domain that is a set and a given codomain is mapped, through evaluation at a point of the domain, onto the codomain. (Contributed by AV, 15-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} & ⊢ 𝑆 = (𝑔 ∈ 𝐹 ↦ (𝑔‘𝑋)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝑆:𝐹–onto→𝐵) | ||
Theorem | fsetprcnex 8608* | The class of all functions from a nonempty set 𝐴 into a proper class 𝐵 is not a set. If one of the preconditions is not fufilled, then {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} is a set, see fsetdmprc0 8601 for 𝐴 ∉ V, fset0 8600 for 𝐴 = ∅, and fsetex 8602 for 𝐵 ∈ V, see also fsetexb 8610. (Contributed by AV, 14-Sep-2024.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 15-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) ∧ 𝐵 ∉ V) → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} ∉ V) | ||
Theorem | fsetcdmex 8609* | The class of all functions from a nonempty set 𝐴 into a class 𝐵 is a set iff 𝐵 is a set . (Contributed by AV, 15-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) → (𝐵 ∈ V ↔ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} ∈ V)) | ||
Theorem | fsetexb 8610* | The class of all functions from a class 𝐴 into a class 𝐵 is a set iff 𝐵 is a set or 𝐴 is not a set or 𝐴 is empty. (Contributed by AV, 15-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ({𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} ∈ V ↔ (𝐴 ∉ V ∨ 𝐴 = ∅ ∨ 𝐵 ∈ V)) | ||
Theorem | elmapfn 8611 | A mapping is a function with the appropriate domain. (Contributed by AV, 6-Apr-2019.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐶) → 𝐴 Fn 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | elmapfun 8612 | A mapping is always a function. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 9-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 5-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐶) → Fun 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | elmapssres 8613 | A restricted mapping is a mapping. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 9-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 5-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐶) ∧ 𝐷 ⊆ 𝐶) → (𝐴 ↾ 𝐷) ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | fpmg 8614 | A total function is a partial function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵) → 𝐹 ∈ (𝐵 ↑pm 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | pmss12g 8615 | Subset relation for the set of partial functions. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ⊆ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐷) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑊)) → (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ⊆ (𝐶 ↑pm 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pmresg 8616 | Elementhood of a restricted function in the set of partial functions. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐶)) → (𝐹 ↾ 𝐵) ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | elmap 8617 | Membership relation for set exponentiation. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2003.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ↔ 𝐹:𝐵⟶𝐴) | ||
Theorem | mapval2 8618* | Alternate expression for the value of set exponentiation. (Contributed by NM, 3-Nov-2007.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) = (𝒫 (𝐵 × 𝐴) ∩ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓 Fn 𝐵}) | ||
Theorem | elpm 8619 | The predicate "is a partial function". (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ↔ (Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐹 ⊆ (𝐵 × 𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | elpm2 8620 | The predicate "is a partial function". (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ↔ (𝐹:dom 𝐹⟶𝐴 ∧ dom 𝐹 ⊆ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | fpm 8621 | A total function is a partial function. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵 → 𝐹 ∈ (𝐵 ↑pm 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | mapsspm 8622 | Set exponentiation is a subset of partial maps. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 27-Feb-2016.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ⊆ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | pmsspw 8623 | Partial maps are a subset of the power set of the Cartesian product of its arguments. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ⊆ 𝒫 (𝐵 × 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | mapsspw 8624 | Set exponentiation is a subset of the power set of the Cartesian product of its arguments. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ⊆ 𝒫 (𝐵 × 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | mapfvd 8625 | The value of a function that maps from 𝐵 to 𝐴. (Contributed by AV, 2-Feb-2023.) |
⊢ 𝑀 = (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ 𝑀) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹‘𝑋) ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | elmapresaun 8626 | fresaun 6629 transposed to mappings. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 9-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ (𝐶 ↑m 𝐴) ∧ 𝐺 ∈ (𝐶 ↑m 𝐵) ∧ (𝐹 ↾ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵)) = (𝐺 ↾ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵))) → (𝐹 ∪ 𝐺) ∈ (𝐶 ↑m (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | fvmptmap 8627* | Special case of fvmpt 6857 for operator theorems. (Contributed by NM, 27-Nov-2007.) |
⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐷 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑅 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝑅 ↑m 𝐷) ↦ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴:𝐷⟶𝑅 → (𝐹‘𝐴) = 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | map0e 8628 | Set exponentiation with an empty exponent (ordinal number 0) is ordinal number 1. Exercise 4.42(a) of [Mendelson] p. 255. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) (Proof shortened by AV, 14-Jul-2022.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ↑m ∅) = 1o) | ||
Theorem | map0b 8629 | Set exponentiation with an empty base is the empty set, provided the exponent is nonempty. Theorem 96 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≠ ∅ → (∅ ↑m 𝐴) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | map0g 8630 | Set exponentiation is empty iff the base is empty and the exponent is not empty. Theorem 97 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → ((𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) = ∅ ↔ (𝐴 = ∅ ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅))) | ||
Theorem | 0map0sn0 8631 | The set of mappings of the empty set to the empty set is the singleton containing the empty set. (Contributed by AV, 31-Mar-2024.) |
⊢ (∅ ↑m ∅) = {∅} | ||
Theorem | mapsnd 8632* | The value of set exponentiation with a singleton exponent. Theorem 98 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Glauco Siliprandi, 24-Dec-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 ↑m {𝐵}) = {𝑓 ∣ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝑓 = {〈𝐵, 𝑦〉}}) | ||
Theorem | map0 8633 | Set exponentiation is empty iff the base is empty and the exponent is not empty. Theorem 97 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2003.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) = ∅ ↔ (𝐴 = ∅ ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅)) | ||
Theorem | mapsn 8634* | The value of set exponentiation with a singleton exponent. Theorem 98 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2003.) (Proof shortened by AV, 17-Jul-2022.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ↑m {𝐵}) = {𝑓 ∣ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝑓 = {〈𝐵, 𝑦〉}} | ||
Theorem | mapss 8635 | Subset inheritance for set exponentiation. Theorem 99 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵) → (𝐴 ↑m 𝐶) ⊆ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | fdiagfn 8636* | Functionality of the diagonal map. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ (𝐼 × {𝑥})) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐼 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝐹:𝐵⟶(𝐵 ↑m 𝐼)) | ||
Theorem | fvdiagfn 8637* | Functionality of the diagonal map. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ (𝐼 × {𝑥})) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐼 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝐹‘𝑋) = (𝐼 × {𝑋})) | ||
Theorem | mapsnconst 8638 | Every singleton map is a constant function. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 25-Mar-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑋} & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝑆) → 𝐹 = (𝑆 × {(𝐹‘𝑋)})) | ||
Theorem | mapsncnv 8639* | Expression for the inverse of the canonical map between a set and its set of singleton functions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Mar-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑋} & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝑆) ↦ (𝑥‘𝑋)) ⇒ ⊢ ◡𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ (𝑆 × {𝑦})) | ||
Theorem | mapsnf1o2 8640* | Explicit bijection between a set and its singleton functions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Mar-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑋} & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝑆) ↦ (𝑥‘𝑋)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹:(𝐵 ↑m 𝑆)–1-1-onto→𝐵 | ||
Theorem | mapsnf1o3 8641* | Explicit bijection in the reverse of mapsnf1o2 8640. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Mar-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑋} & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ (𝑆 × {𝑦})) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹:𝐵–1-1-onto→(𝐵 ↑m 𝑆) | ||
Theorem | ralxpmap 8642* | Quantification over functions in terms of quantification over values and punctured functions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 27-Feb-2015.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 5-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑓 = (𝑔 ∪ {〈𝐽, 𝑦〉}) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐽 ∈ 𝑇 → (∀𝑓 ∈ (𝑆 ↑m 𝑇)𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑆 ∀𝑔 ∈ (𝑆 ↑m (𝑇 ∖ {𝐽}))𝜓)) | ||
Syntax | cixp 8643 | Extend class notation to include infinite Cartesian products. |
class X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 | ||
Definition | df-ixp 8644* | Definition of infinite Cartesian product of [Enderton] p. 54. Enderton uses a bold "X" with 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 written underneath or as a subscript, as does Stoll p. 47. Some books use a capital pi, but we will reserve that notation for products of numbers. Usually 𝐵 represents a class expression containing 𝑥 free and thus can be thought of as 𝐵(𝑥). Normally, 𝑥 is not free in 𝐴, although this is not a requirement of the definition. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = {𝑓 ∣ (𝑓 Fn {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴} ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑓‘𝑥) ∈ 𝐵)} | ||
Theorem | dfixp 8645* | Eliminate the expression {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴} in df-ixp 8644, under the assumption that 𝐴 and 𝑥 are disjoint. This way, we can say that 𝑥 is bound in X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴𝐵 even if it appears free in 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = {𝑓 ∣ (𝑓 Fn 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑓‘𝑥) ∈ 𝐵)} | ||
Theorem | ixpsnval 8646* | The value of an infinite Cartesian product with a singleton. (Contributed by AV, 3-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ 𝑉 → X𝑥 ∈ {𝑋}𝐵 = {𝑓 ∣ (𝑓 Fn {𝑋} ∧ (𝑓‘𝑋) ∈ ⦋𝑋 / 𝑥⦌𝐵)}) | ||
Theorem | elixp2 8647* | Membership in an infinite Cartesian product. See df-ixp 8644 for discussion of the notation. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↔ (𝐹 ∈ V ∧ 𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐹‘𝑥) ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | fvixp 8648* | Projection of a factor of an indexed Cartesian product. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐶 → 𝐵 = 𝐷) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐹‘𝐶) ∈ 𝐷) | ||
Theorem | ixpfn 8649* | A nuple is a function. (Contributed by FL, 6-Jun-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-May-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 → 𝐹 Fn 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | elixp 8650* | Membership in an infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ 𝐹 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↔ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐹‘𝑥) ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | elixpconst 8651* | Membership in an infinite Cartesian product of a constant 𝐵. (Contributed by NM, 12-Apr-2008.) |
⊢ 𝐹 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↔ 𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵) | ||
Theorem | ixpconstg 8652* | Infinite Cartesian product of a constant 𝐵. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = (𝐵 ↑m 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ixpconst 8653* | Infinite Cartesian product of a constant 𝐵. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = (𝐵 ↑m 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ixpeq1 8654* | Equality theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 29-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpeq1d 8655* | Equality theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ss2ixp 8656 | Subclass theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 29-Sep-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐶 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ⊆ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpeq2 8657 | Equality theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 29-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = 𝐶 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpeq2dva 8658* | Equality theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpeq2dv 8659* | Equality theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | cbvixp 8660* | Change bound variable in an indexed Cartesian product. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 20-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐵 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐶 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = X𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 | ||
Theorem | cbvixpv 8661* | Change bound variable in an indexed Cartesian product. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = X𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 | ||
Theorem | nfixpw 8662* | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for indexed Cartesian product. Version of nfixp 8663 with a disjoint variable condition, which does not require ax-13 2372. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Gino Giotto, 26-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 | ||
Theorem | nfixp 8663 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for indexed Cartesian product. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2372. Use the weaker nfixpw 8662 when possible. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 | ||
Theorem | nfixp1 8664 | The index variable in an indexed Cartesian product is not free. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 19-Jun-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 | ||
Theorem | ixpprc 8665* | A cartesian product of proper-class many sets is empty, because any function in the cartesian product has to be a set with domain 𝐴, which is not possible for a proper class domain. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 25-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝐴 ∈ V → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = ∅) | ||
Theorem | ixpf 8666* | A member of an infinite Cartesian product maps to the indexed union of the product argument. Remark in [Enderton] p. 54. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 → 𝐹:𝐴⟶∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | uniixp 8667* | The union of an infinite Cartesian product is included in a Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ∪ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ⊆ (𝐴 × ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | ixpexg 8668* | The existence of an infinite Cartesian product. 𝑥 is normally a free-variable parameter in 𝐵. Remark in Enderton p. 54. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 25-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | ixpin 8669* | The intersection of two infinite Cartesian products. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐵 ∩ 𝐶) = (X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∩ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpiin 8670* | The indexed intersection of a collection of infinite Cartesian products. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ≠ ∅ → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∩ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶 = ∩ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpint 8671* | The intersection of a collection of infinite Cartesian products. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ≠ ∅ → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∩ 𝐵 = ∩ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑦) | ||
Theorem | ixp0x 8672 | An infinite Cartesian product with an empty index set. (Contributed by NM, 21-Sep-2007.) |
⊢ X𝑥 ∈ ∅ 𝐴 = {∅} | ||
Theorem | ixpssmap2g 8673* | An infinite Cartesian product is a subset of set exponentiation. This version of ixpssmapg 8674 avoids ax-rep 5205. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ⊆ (∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↑m 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ixpssmapg 8674* | An infinite Cartesian product is a subset of set exponentiation. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 19-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ⊆ (∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↑m 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | 0elixp 8675 | Membership of the empty set in an infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by Steve Rodriguez, 29-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ ∅ ∈ X𝑥 ∈ ∅ 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | ixpn0 8676 | The infinite Cartesian product of a family 𝐵(𝑥) with an empty member is empty. The converse of this theorem is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice, see ac9 10170. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ≠ ∅ → ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ≠ ∅) | ||
Theorem | ixp0 8677 | The infinite Cartesian product of a family 𝐵(𝑥) with an empty member is empty. The converse of this theorem is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice, see ac9 10170. (Contributed by NM, 1-Oct-2006.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = ∅ → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = ∅) | ||
Theorem | ixpssmap 8678* | An infinite Cartesian product is a subset of set exponentiation. Remark in [Enderton] p. 54. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ⊆ (∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↑m 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | resixp 8679* | Restriction of an element of an infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by FL, 7-Nov-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 31-May-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) → (𝐹 ↾ 𝐵) ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | undifixp 8680* | Union of two projections of a cartesian product. (Contributed by FL, 7-Nov-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶 ∧ 𝐺 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 ∖ 𝐵)𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) → (𝐹 ∪ 𝐺) ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | mptelixpg 8681* | Condition for an explicit member of an indexed product. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 4-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐼 ∈ 𝑉 → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 ↦ 𝐽) ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 𝐾 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 𝐽 ∈ 𝐾)) | ||
Theorem | resixpfo 8682* | Restriction of elements of an infinite Cartesian product creates a surjection, if the original Cartesian product is nonempty. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑓 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 ↦ (𝑓 ↾ 𝐵)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 ≠ ∅) → 𝐹:X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶–onto→X𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | elixpsn 8683* | Membership in a class of singleton functions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ {𝐴}𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝐹 = {〈𝐴, 𝑦〉})) | ||
Theorem | ixpsnf1o 8684* | A bijection between a class and single-point functions to it. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ ({𝐼} × {𝑥})) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐼 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→X𝑦 ∈ {𝐼}𝐴) | ||
Theorem | mapsnf1o 8685* | A bijection between a set and single-point functions to it. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ ({𝐼} × {𝑥})) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐼 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→(𝐴 ↑m {𝐼})) | ||
Theorem | boxriin 8686* | A rectangular subset of a rectangular set can be recovered as the relative intersection of single-axis restrictions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 𝐴 = (X𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 𝐵 ∩ ∩ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐼 X𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 if(𝑥 = 𝑦, 𝐴, 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | boxcutc 8687* | The relative complement of a box set restricted on one axis. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 ⊆ 𝐵) → (X𝑘 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∖ X𝑘 ∈ 𝐴 if(𝑘 = 𝑋, 𝐶, 𝐵)) = X𝑘 ∈ 𝐴 if(𝑘 = 𝑋, (𝐵 ∖ 𝐶), 𝐵)) | ||
Syntax | cen 8688 | Extend class definition to include the equinumerosity relation ("approximately equals" symbol) |
class ≈ | ||
Syntax | cdom 8689 | Extend class definition to include the dominance relation (curly "less than or equal to") |
class ≼ | ||
Syntax | csdm 8690 | Extend class definition to include the strict dominance relation (curly less-than) |
class ≺ | ||
Syntax | cfn 8691 | Extend class definition to include the class of all finite sets. |
class Fin | ||
Definition | df-en 8692* | Define the equinumerosity relation. Definition of [Enderton] p. 129. We define ≈ to be a binary relation rather than a connective, so its arguments must be sets to be meaningful. This is acceptable because we do not consider equinumerosity for proper classes. We derive the usual definition as bren 8701. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ ≈ = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝑥–1-1-onto→𝑦} | ||
Definition | df-dom 8693* | Define the dominance relation. For an alternate definition see dfdom2 8721. Compare Definition of [Enderton] p. 145. Typical textbook definitions are derived as brdom 8705 and domen 8706. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ ≼ = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝑥–1-1→𝑦} | ||
Definition | df-sdom 8694 | Define the strict dominance relation. Alternate possible definitions are derived as brsdom 8718 and brsdom2 8837. Definition 3 of [Suppes] p. 97. (Contributed by NM, 31-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ ≺ = ( ≼ ∖ ≈ ) | ||
Definition | df-fin 8695* | Define the (proper) class of all finite sets. Similar to Definition 10.29 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 91, whose "Fin(a)" corresponds to our "𝑎 ∈ Fin". This definition is meaningful whether or not we accept the Axiom of Infinity ax-inf2 9329. If we accept Infinity, we can also express 𝐴 ∈ Fin by 𝐴 ≺ ω (Theorem isfinite 9340.) (Contributed by NM, 22-Aug-2008.) |
⊢ Fin = {𝑥 ∣ ∃𝑦 ∈ ω 𝑥 ≈ 𝑦} | ||
Theorem | relen 8696 | Equinumerosity is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ Rel ≈ | ||
Theorem | reldom 8697 | Dominance is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ Rel ≼ | ||
Theorem | relsdom 8698 | Strict dominance is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 31-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ Rel ≺ | ||
Theorem | encv 8699 | If two classes are equinumerous, both classes are sets. (Contributed by AV, 21-Mar-2019.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 → (𝐴 ∈ V ∧ 𝐵 ∈ V)) | ||
Theorem | breng 8700* | Equinumerosity relation. This variation of bren 8701 does not require the Axiom of Union. (Contributed by BTernaryTau, 23-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵)) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |