Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 1 of 466) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29280) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29281-30803) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30804-46521) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Logic can be defined as the "study of the principles of correct reasoning" (Merrilee H. Salmon's 1991 "Informal Reasoning and Informal Logic" in Informal Reasoning and Education) or as "a formal system using symbolic techniques and mathematical methods to establish truth-values" (the Oxford English Dictionary). This section formally defines the logic system we will use. In particular, it defines symbols for declaring truthful statements, along with rules for deriving truthful statements from other truthful statements. The system defined here is classical first-order logic (often abbreviated as FOL) with equality and no terms (the most common logic system used by mathematicians). We begin with a few housekeeping items in pre-logic, and then introduce propositional calculus (both its axioms and important theorems that can be derived from them). Propositional calculus deals with general truths about well-formed formulas (wffs) regardless of how they are constructed. This is followed by proofs that other axiomatizations of classical propositional calculus can be derived from the axioms we have chosen to use. We then define predicate calculus, which adds additional symbols and rules useful for discussing objects (beyond simply true or false). In particular, it introduces the symbols = ("equals"), ∈ ("is a member of"), and ∀ ("for all"). The first two are called "predicates". A predicate specifies a true or false relationship between its two arguments. | ||
This section includes a few "housekeeping" mechanisms before we begin defining the basics of logic. | ||
The inference rules in this section will normally never appear in a completed proof. They can be ignored if you are using this database to assist learning logic - please start with the statement wn 3 instead. | ||
Theorem | idi 1 |
(Note: This inference rule and the next one, a1ii 2,
will normally
never appear in a completed proof. They can be ignored if you are using
this database to assist learning logic; please start with the statement
wn 3 instead.)
This inference says "if 𝜑 is true then 𝜑 is true". This inference requires no axioms for its proof, and is useful as a copy-paste mechanism during proof development in mmj2. It is normally not referenced in the final version of a proof, since it is always redundant. You can remove this using the metamath-exe (Metamath program) Proof Assistant using the "MM-PA> MINIMIZE_WITH *" command. This is the inference associated with id 22, hence its name. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 31-Dec-2011.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | a1ii 2 |
(Note: This inference rule and the previous one, idi 1, will
normally never appear in a completed proof.)
This is a technical inference to assist proof development. It provides
a temporary way to add an independent subproof to a proof under
development, for later assignment to a normal proof step.
The Metamath (Metamath-exe) program Proof Assistant requires proofs to
be developed backwards from the conclusion with no gaps, and it has no
mechanism that lets the user work on isolated subproofs. This inference
provides a workaround for this limitation. It can be inserted at any
point in a proof to allow an independent subproof to be developed on the
side, for later use as part of the final proof.
Instructions:
This can also be used to apply subproofs from other theorems. In step
2, simply assign the theorem to a1ii.2, and run
This inference was originally designed to assist importing partially completed Proof Worksheets from the mmj2 Proof Assistant GUI, but it can also be useful on its own. Interestingly, no axioms are required for its proof. It is the inference associated with a1i 11. (Contributed by NM, 7-Feb-2006.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ 𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Propositional calculus deals with general truths about well-formed formulas (wffs) regardless of how they are constructed. The simplest propositional truth is (𝜑 → 𝜑), which can be read "if something is true, then it is true" - rather trivial and obvious, but nonetheless it must be proved from the axioms (see Theorem id 22). Our system of propositional calculus consists of three basic axioms and another axiom that defines the modus-ponens inference rule. It is attributed to Jan Lukasiewicz (pronounced woo-kah-SHAY-vitch) and was popularized by Alonzo Church, who called it system P2. (Thanks to Ted Ulrich for this information.) These axioms are ax-1 6, ax-2 7, ax-3 8, and (for modus ponens) ax-mp 5. Some closely followed texts include [Margaris] for the axioms and [WhiteheadRussell] for the theorems. The propositional calculus used here is the classical system widely used by mathematicians. In particular, this logic system accepts the "law of the excluded middle" as proven in exmid 892, which says that a logical statement is either true or not true. This is an essential distinction of classical logic and is not a theorem of intuitionistic logic. All 194 axioms, definitions, and theorems for propositional calculus in Principia Mathematica (specifically *1.2 through *5.75) are axioms or formally proven. See the Bibliographic Cross-References at mmbiblio.html 892 for a complete cross-reference from sources used to its formalization in the Metamath Proof Explorer. | ||
Syntax | wn 3 | If 𝜑 is a wff, so is ¬ 𝜑 or "not 𝜑". Part of the recursive definition of a wff (well-formed formula). In classical logic (which is our logic), a wff is interpreted as either true or false. So if 𝜑 is true, then ¬ 𝜑 is false; if 𝜑 is false, then ¬ 𝜑 is true. Traditionally, Greek letters are used to represent wffs, and we follow this convention. In propositional calculus, we define only wffs built up from other wffs, i.e. there is no starting or "atomic" wff. Later, in predicate calculus, we will extend the basic wff definition by including atomic wffs (weq 1966 and wel 2107). |
wff ¬ 𝜑 | ||
Syntax | wi 4 |
If 𝜑
and 𝜓
are wff's, so is (𝜑 → 𝜓) or "𝜑 implies
𝜓". Part of the recursive
definition of a wff. The resulting wff
is (interpreted as) false when 𝜑 is true and 𝜓 is false; it is
true otherwise. Think of the truth table for an OR gate with input 𝜑
connected through an inverter. After we state the axioms of propositional
calculus (ax-1 6, ax-2 7, ax-3 8, and ax-mp 5) and define the
biconditional (df-bi 206), the constant true ⊤ (df-tru 1542), and the
constant false ⊥ (df-fal 1552), we will be able to prove these truth
table values: ((⊤ → ⊤) ↔
⊤) (truimtru 1562),
((⊤ → ⊥) ↔ ⊥) (truimfal 1563), ((⊥ → ⊤)
↔ ⊤)
(falimtru 1564), and ((⊥ →
⊥) ↔ ⊤) (falimfal 1565). These
have straightforward meanings, for example, ((⊤
→ ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
just means "the value of (⊤ →
⊤) is ⊤".
The left-hand wff is called the antecedent, and the right-hand wff is called the consequent. In the case of (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)), the middle 𝜓 may be informally called either an antecedent or part of the consequent depending on context. Contrast with ↔ (df-bi 206), ∧ (df-an 397), and ∨ (df-or 845). This is called "material implication" and the arrow is usually read as "implies". However, material implication is not identical to the meaning of "implies" in natural language. For example, the word "implies" may suggest a causal relationship in natural language. Material implication does not require any causal relationship. Also, note that in material implication, if the consequent is true then the wff is always true (even if the antecedent is false). Thus, if "implies" means material implication, it is true that "if the moon is made of green cheese that implies that 5=5" (because 5=5). Similarly, if the antecedent is false, the wff is always true. Thus, it is true that, "if the moon is made of green cheese that implies that 5=7" (because the moon is not actually made of green cheese). A contradiction implies anything (pm2.21i 119). In short, material implication has a very specific technical definition, and misunderstandings of it are sometimes called "paradoxes of logical implication". |
wff (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Propositional calculus (Axioms ax-1 6 through ax-3 8 and rule ax-mp 5) can be thought of as asserting formulas that are universally "true" when their variables are replaced by any combination of "true" and "false". Propositional calculus was first formalized by Frege in 1879, using as his axioms (in addition to rule ax-mp 5) the wffs ax-1 6, ax-2 7, pm2.04 90, con3 153, notnot 142, and notnotr 130. Around 1930, Lukasiewicz simplified the system by eliminating the third (which follows from the first two, as you can see by looking at the proof of pm2.04 90) and replacing the last three with our ax-3 8. (Thanks to Ted Ulrich for this information.) The theorems of propositional calculus are also called tautologies. Tautologies can be proved very simply using truth tables, based on the true/false interpretation of propositional calculus. To do this, we assign all possible combinations of true and false to the wff variables and verify that the result (using the rules described in wi 4 and wn 3) always evaluates to true. This is called the semantic approach. Our approach is called the syntactic approach, in which everything is derived from axioms. A metatheorem called the Completeness Theorem for Propositional Calculus shows that the two approaches are equivalent and even provides an algorithm for automatically generating syntactic proofs from a truth table. Those proofs, however, tend to be long, since truth tables grow exponentially with the number of variables, and the much shorter proofs that we show here were found manually. | ||
Axiom | ax-mp 5 |
Rule of Modus Ponens. The postulated inference rule of propositional
calculus. See, e.g., Rule 1 of [Hamilton] p. 73. The rule says, "if
𝜑 is true, and 𝜑 implies 𝜓, then
𝜓
must also be
true". This rule is sometimes called "detachment", since
it detaches
the minor premise from the major premise. "Modus ponens" is
short for
"modus ponendo ponens", a Latin phrase that means "the
mode that by
affirming affirms" - remark in [Sanford] p. 39. This rule is similar to
the rule of modus tollens mto 196.
Note: In some web page displays such as the Statement List, the symbols "& " and "⇒ " informally indicate the relationship between the hypotheses and the assertion (conclusion), abbreviating the English words "and" and "implies". They are not part of the formal language. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-1992.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Axiom | ax-1 6 | Axiom Simp. Axiom A1 of [Margaris] p. 49. One of the 3 axioms of propositional calculus. The 3 axioms are also given as Definition 2.1 of [Hamilton] p. 28. This axiom is called Simp or "the principle of simplification" in Principia Mathematica (Theorem *2.02 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 100) because "it enables us to pass from the joint assertion of 𝜑 and 𝜓 to the assertion of 𝜑 simply". It is Proposition 1 of [Frege1879] p. 26, its first axiom. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-1992.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜑)) | ||
Axiom | ax-2 7 | Axiom Frege. Axiom A2 of [Margaris] p. 49. One of the 3 axioms of propositional calculus. It "distributes" an antecedent over two consequents. This axiom was part of Frege's original system and is known as Frege in the literature; see Proposition 2 of [Frege1879] p. 26. It is also proved as Theorem *2.77 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 108. The other direction of this axiom also turns out to be true, as demonstrated by pm5.41 392. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-1992.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||
Axiom | ax-3 8 | Axiom Transp. Axiom A3 of [Margaris] p. 49. One of the 3 axioms of propositional calculus. It swaps or "transposes" the order of the consequents when negation is removed. An informal example is that the statement "if there are no clouds in the sky, it is not raining" implies the statement "if it is raining, there are clouds in the sky". This axiom is called Transp or "the principle of transposition" in Principia Mathematica (Theorem *2.17 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 103). We will also use the term "contraposition" for this principle, although the reader is advised that in the field of philosophical logic, "contraposition" has a different technical meaning. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-1992.) Use its alias con4 113 instead. (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((¬ 𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) → (𝜓 → 𝜑)) | ||
The results in this section are based on implication only, and avoid ax-3 8, so are intuitionistic. The system { ax-mp 5, ax-1 6, ax-2 7 } axiomatizes what is sometimes called "intuitionistic implicational calculus" or "minimal implicational calculus". In an implication, the wff before the arrow is called the "antecedent" and the wff after the arrow is called the "consequent". | ||
Theorem | mp2 9 | A double modus ponens inference. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜒 | ||
Theorem | mp2b 10 | A double modus ponens inference. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜒 | ||
Theorem | a1i 11 | Inference introducing an antecedent. Inference associated with ax-1 6. Its associated inference is a1ii 2. See conventions 28764 for a definition of "associated inference". (Contributed by NM, 29-Dec-1992.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 2a1i 12 | Inference introducing two antecedents. Two applications of a1i 11. Inference associated with 2a1 28. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 4-Aug-2009.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | mp1i 13 | Inference detaching an antecedent and introducing a new one. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 29-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | a2i 14 | Inference distributing an antecedent. Inference associated with ax-2 7. Its associated inference is mpd 15. (Contributed by NM, 29-Dec-1992.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | mpd 15 | A modus ponens deduction. A translation of natural deduction rule → E (→ elimination), see natded 28767. Deduction form of ax-mp 5. Inference associated with a2i 14. Commuted form of mpcom 38. (Contributed by NM, 29-Dec-1992.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | imim2i 16 | Inference adding common antecedents in an implication. Inference associated with imim2 58. Its associated inference is syl 17. (Contributed by NM, 28-Dec-1992.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜒 → 𝜑) → (𝜒 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | syl 17 |
An inference version of the transitive laws for implication imim2 58
and
imim1 83 (and imim1i 63 and imim2i 16), which Russell and Whitehead call
"the principle of the syllogism ... because ... the syllogism in
Barbara
is derived from [syl 17]" (quote after Theorem *2.06 of
[WhiteheadRussell] p. 101).
Some authors call this law a "hypothetical
syllogism". Its associated inference is mp2b 10.
(A bit of trivia: this is the most commonly referenced assertion in our database (13449 times as of 22-Jul-2021). In second place is eqid 2738 (9597 times), followed by adantr 481 (8861 times), syl2anc 584 (7421 times), adantl 482 (6403 times), and simpr 485 (5829 times). The Metamath program command 'show usage' shows the number of references.) (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-1992.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 20-Oct-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 26-Jul-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | 3syl 18 | Inference chaining two syllogisms syl 17. Inference associated with imim12i 62. (Contributed by NM, 28-Dec-1992.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | 4syl 19 | Inference chaining three syllogisms syl 17. (Contributed by BJ, 14-Jul-2018.) The use of this theorem is marked "discouraged" because it can cause the Metamath program "MM-PA> MINIMIZE_WITH *" command to have very long run times. However, feel free to use "MM-PA> MINIMIZE_WITH 4syl / OVERRIDE" if you wish. Remember to update the "discouraged" file if it gets used. (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜃) & ⊢ (𝜃 → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | mpi 20 | A nested modus ponens inference. Inference associated with com12 32. (Contributed by NM, 29-Dec-1992.) (Proof shortened by Stefan Allan, 20-Mar-2006.) |
⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | mpisyl 21 | A syllogism combined with a modus ponens inference. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 25-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ 𝜒 & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | id 22 | Principle of identity. Theorem *2.08 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 101. For another version of the proof directly from axioms, see idALT 23. Its associated inference, idi 1, requires no axioms for its proof, contrary to id 22. Note that the second occurrences of 𝜑 in Steps 1 and 2 may be simultaneously replaced by any wff 𝜓, which may ease the understanding of the proof. (Contributed by NM, 29-Dec-1992.) (Proof shortened by Stefan Allan, 20-Mar-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | idALT 23 | Alternate proof of id 22. This version is proved directly from the axioms for demonstration purposes. This proof is a popular example in the literature and is identical, step for step, to the proofs of Theorem 1 of [Margaris] p. 51, Example 2.7(a) of [Hamilton] p. 31, Lemma 10.3 of [BellMachover] p. 36, and Lemma 1.8 of [Mendelson] p. 36. It is also "Our first proof" in Hirst and Hirst's A Primer for Logic and Proof p. 17 (PDF p. 23) at http://www.appstate.edu/~hirstjl/primer/hirst.pdf 22. Note that the second occurrences of 𝜑 in Steps 1 to 4 and the sixth in Step 3 may be simultaneously replaced by any wff 𝜓, which may ease the understanding of the proof. For a shorter version of the proof that takes advantage of previously proved theorems, see id 22. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-1992.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) Use id 22 instead. (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | idd 24 | Principle of identity id 22 with antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 26-Nov-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | a1d 25 | Deduction introducing an embedded antecedent. Deduction form of ax-1 6 and a1i 11. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jan-1993.) (Proof shortened by Stefan Allan, 20-Mar-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 2a1d 26 | Deduction introducing two antecedents. Two applications of a1d 25. Deduction associated with 2a1 28 and 2a1i 12. (Contributed by BJ, 10-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | a1i13 27 | Add two antecedents to a wff. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 4-Aug-2009.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | 2a1 28 | A double form of ax-1 6. Its associated inference is 2a1i 12. Its associated deduction is 2a1d 26. (Contributed by BJ, 10-Aug-2020.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 1-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | a2d 29 | Deduction distributing an embedded antecedent. Deduction form of ax-2 7. (Contributed by NM, 23-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → (𝜓 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | sylcom 30 | Syllogism inference with commutation of antecedents. (Contributed by NM, 29-Aug-2004.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 2-Feb-2006.) (Proof shortened by Stefan Allan, 23-Feb-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | syl5com 31 | Syllogism inference with commuted antecedents. (Contributed by NM, 24-May-2005.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | com12 32 | Inference that swaps (commutes) antecedents in an implication. Inference associated with pm2.04 90. Its associated inference is mpi 20. (Contributed by NM, 29-Dec-1992.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 4-Aug-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | syl11 33 | A syllogism inference. Commuted form of an instance of syl 17. (Contributed by BJ, 25-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜃 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | syl5 34 | A syllogism rule of inference. The first premise is used to replace the second antecedent of the second premise. (Contributed by NM, 27-Dec-1992.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 25-May-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | syl6 35 | A syllogism rule of inference. The second premise is used to replace the consequent of the first premise. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jan-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 30-Jul-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | syl56 36 | Combine syl5 34 and syl6 35. (Contributed by NM, 14-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜃 → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | syl6com 37 | Syllogism inference with commuted antecedents. (Contributed by NM, 25-May-2005.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | mpcom 38 | Modus ponens inference with commutation of antecedents. Commuted form of mpd 15. (Contributed by NM, 17-Mar-1996.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | syli 39 | Syllogism inference with common nested antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2004.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | syl2im 40 | Replace two antecedents. Implication-only version of syl2an 596. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 14-May-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜃) & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | syl2imc 41 | A commuted version of syl2im 40. Implication-only version of syl2anr 597. (Contributed by BJ, 20-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜃) & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | pm2.27 42 | This theorem, sometimes called "Assertion" or "Pon" (for "ponens"), can be thought of as a closed form of modus ponens ax-mp 5. Theorem *2.27 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 104. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jul-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | mpdd 43 | A nested modus ponens deduction. Double deduction associated with ax-mp 5. Deduction associated with mpd 15. (Contributed by NM, 12-Dec-2004.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | mpid 44 | A nested modus ponens deduction. Deduction associated with mpi 20. (Contributed by NM, 14-Dec-2004.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | mpdi 45 | A nested modus ponens deduction. (Contributed by NM, 16-Apr-2005.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 15-Jan-2008.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | mpii 46 | A doubly nested modus ponens inference. (Contributed by NM, 31-Dec-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 31-Jul-2012.) |
⊢ 𝜒 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | syld 47 | Syllogism deduction. Deduction associated with syl 17. See conventions 28764 for the meaning of "associated deduction" or "deduction form". (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 19-Feb-2008.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 3-Aug-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | syldc 48 | Syllogism deduction. Commuted form of syld 47. (Contributed by BJ, 25-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | mp2d 49 | A double modus ponens deduction. Deduction associated with mp2 9. (Contributed by NM, 23-May-2013.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 23-Jul-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | a1dd 50 | Double deduction introducing an antecedent. Deduction associated with a1d 25. Double deduction associated with ax-1 6 and a1i 11. (Contributed by NM, 17-Dec-2004.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 15-Jan-2008.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | 2a1dd 51 | Double deduction introducing two antecedents. Two applications of 2a1dd 51. Deduction associated with 2a1d 26. Double deduction associated with 2a1 28 and 2a1i 12. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 5-Aug-2009.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → (𝜏 → 𝜒)))) | ||
Theorem | pm2.43i 52 | Inference absorbing redundant antecedent. Inference associated with pm2.43 56. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jan-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 28-Nov-2008.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | pm2.43d 53 | Deduction absorbing redundant antecedent. Deduction associated with pm2.43 56 and pm2.43i 52. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 28-Nov-2008.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜓 → 𝜒))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | pm2.43a 54 | Inference absorbing redundant antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 7-Nov-1995.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 28-Nov-2008.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | pm2.43b 55 | Inference absorbing redundant antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 31-Oct-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | pm2.43 56 | Absorption of redundant antecedent. Also called the "Contraction" or "Hilbert" axiom. Theorem *2.43 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 106. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jan-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 15-Aug-2004.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | imim2d 57 | Deduction adding nested antecedents. Deduction associated with imim2 58 and imim2i 16. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jan-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜃 → 𝜓) → (𝜃 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | imim2 58 | A closed form of syllogism (see syl 17). Theorem *2.05 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 100. Its associated inference is imim2i 16. Its associated deduction is imim2d 57. An alternate proof from more basic results is given by ax-1 6 followed by a2d 29. (Contributed by NM, 29-Dec-1992.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 6-Sep-2012.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜒 → 𝜑) → (𝜒 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | embantd 59 | Deduction embedding an antecedent. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 4-Oct-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | 3syld 60 | Triple syllogism deduction. Deduction associated with 3syld 60. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 4-Aug-2009.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | sylsyld 61 | A double syllogism inference. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 20-Apr-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | imim12i 62 | Inference joining two implications. Inference associated with imim12 105. Its associated inference is 3syl 18. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 29-Oct-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → (𝜑 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | imim1i 63 | Inference adding common consequents in an implication, thereby interchanging the original antecedent and consequent. Inference associated with imim1 83. Its associated inference is syl 17. (Contributed by NM, 28-Dec-1992.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 4-Aug-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | imim3i 64 | Inference adding three nested antecedents. (Contributed by NM, 19-Dec-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜃 → 𝜑) → ((𝜃 → 𝜓) → (𝜃 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | sylc 65 | A syllogism inference combined with contraction. (Contributed by NM, 4-May-1994.) (Revised by NM, 13-Jul-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | syl3c 66 | A syllogism inference combined with contraction. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 7-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | syl6mpi 67 | A syllogism inference. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 8-Jul-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-Sep-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ 𝜃 & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | mpsyl 68 | Modus ponens combined with a syllogism inference. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 20-Apr-2011.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | mpsylsyld 69 | Modus ponens combined with a double syllogism inference. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 22-Jul-2012.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | syl6c 70 | Inference combining syl6 35 with contraction. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 2-May-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | syl6ci 71 | A syllogism inference combined with contraction. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 18-Mar-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | syldd 72 | Nested syllogism deduction. Deduction associated with syld 47. Double deduction associated with syl 17. (Contributed by NM, 12-Dec-2004.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-May-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜏))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | syl5d 73 | A nested syllogism deduction. Deduction associated with syl5 34. (Contributed by NM, 14-May-1993.) (Proof shortened by Josh Purinton, 29-Dec-2000.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 2-Feb-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → (𝜒 → 𝜏))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → (𝜓 → 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | syl7 74 | A syllogism rule of inference. The first premise is used to replace the third antecedent of the second premise. (Contributed by NM, 12-Jan-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 3-Aug-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜃 → (𝜓 → 𝜏))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜃 → (𝜑 → 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | syl6d 75 | A nested syllogism deduction. Deduction associated with syl6 35. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.) (Proof shortened by Josh Purinton, 29-Dec-2000.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 2-Feb-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | syl8 76 | A syllogism rule of inference. The second premise is used to replace the consequent of the first premise. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 3-Aug-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) & ⊢ (𝜃 → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | syl9 77 | A nested syllogism inference with different antecedents. (Contributed by NM, 13-May-1993.) (Proof shortened by Josh Purinton, 29-Dec-2000.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜃 → (𝜒 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → (𝜓 → 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | syl9r 78 | A nested syllogism inference with different antecedents. (Contributed by NM, 14-May-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜃 → (𝜒 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜃 → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | syl10 79 | A nested syllogism inference. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 17-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜏))) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜏 → 𝜂)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜂))) | ||
Theorem | a1ddd 80 | Triple deduction introducing an antecedent to a wff. Deduction associated with a1dd 50. Double deduction associated with a1d 25. Triple deduction associated with ax-1 6 and a1i 11. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 4-Aug-2009.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜏))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)))) | ||
Theorem | imim12d 81 | Deduction combining antecedents and consequents. Deduction associated with imim12 105 and imim12i 62. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 30-Oct-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜒 → 𝜃) → (𝜓 → 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | imim1d 82 | Deduction adding nested consequents. Deduction associated with imim1 83 and imim1i 63. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-Sep-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜒 → 𝜃) → (𝜓 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | imim1 83 | A closed form of syllogism (see syl 17). Theorem *2.06 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 100. Its associated inference is imim1i 63. (Contributed by NM, 29-Dec-1992.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 25-May-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | pm2.83 84 | Theorem *2.83 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 108. Closed form of syld 47. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2005.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → ((𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)))) | ||
Theorem | peirceroll 85 | Over minimal implicational calculus, Peirce's axiom peirce 201 implies an axiom sometimes called "Roll", (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) → ((𝜒 → 𝜑) → 𝜑)), of which looinv 202 is a special instance. The converse also holds: substitute (𝜑 → 𝜓) for 𝜒 in Roll and use id 22 and ax-mp 5. (Contributed by BJ, 15-Jun-2021.) |
⊢ ((((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜑) → 𝜑) → (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) → ((𝜒 → 𝜑) → 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | com23 86 | Commutation of antecedents. Swap 2nd and 3rd. Deduction associated with com12 32. (Contributed by NM, 27-Dec-1992.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 4-Aug-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | com3r 87 | Commutation of antecedents. Rotate right. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | com13 88 | Commutation of antecedents. Swap 1st and 3rd. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 28-Jul-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | com3l 89 | Commutation of antecedents. Rotate left. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 28-Jul-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | pm2.04 90 | Swap antecedents. Theorem *2.04 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 100. This was the third axiom in Frege's logic system, specifically Proposition 8 of [Frege1879] p. 35. Its associated inference is com12 32. (Contributed by NM, 27-Dec-1992.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-Sep-2012.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | com34 91 | Commutation of antecedents. Swap 3rd and 4th. Deduction associated with com23 86. Double deduction associated with com12 32. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → (𝜒 → 𝜏)))) | ||
Theorem | com4l 92 | Commutation of antecedents. Rotate left. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-1994.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 15-Aug-2004.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → (𝜑 → 𝜏)))) | ||
Theorem | com4t 93 | Commutation of antecedents. Rotate twice. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜃 → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜏)))) | ||
Theorem | com4r 94 | Commutation of antecedents. Rotate right. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜃 → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜏)))) | ||
Theorem | com24 95 | Commutation of antecedents. Swap 2nd and 4th. Deduction associated with com13 88. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 28-Jul-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → (𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜏)))) | ||
Theorem | com14 96 | Commutation of antecedents. Swap 1st and 4th. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 28-Jul-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜃 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜏)))) | ||
Theorem | com45 97 | Commutation of antecedents. Swap 4th and 5th. Deduction associated with com34 91. Double deduction associated with com23 86. Triple deduction associated with com12 32. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 28-Jun-2009.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → (𝜏 → 𝜂))))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜏 → (𝜃 → 𝜂))))) | ||
Theorem | com35 98 | Commutation of antecedents. Swap 3rd and 5th. Deduction associated with com24 95. Double deduction associated with com13 88. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 28-Jun-2009.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → (𝜏 → 𝜂))))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜏 → (𝜃 → (𝜒 → 𝜂))))) | ||
Theorem | com25 99 | Commutation of antecedents. Swap 2nd and 5th. Deduction associated with com14 96. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 28-Jun-2009.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → (𝜏 → 𝜂))))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜏 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → (𝜓 → 𝜂))))) | ||
Theorem | com5l 100 | Commutation of antecedents. Rotate left. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 28-Jun-2009.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 29-Jul-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → (𝜏 → 𝜂))))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → (𝜏 → (𝜑 → 𝜂))))) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |