Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 105 of 464) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29181) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29182-30704) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30705-46395) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | wundif 10401 | A weak universe is closed under class difference. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 ∖ 𝐵) ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunint 10402 | A weak universe is closed under nonempty intersections. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) → ∩ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunsn 10403 | A weak universe is closed under singletons. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → {𝐴} ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunsuc 10404 | A weak universe is closed under successors. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → suc 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wun0 10405 | A weak universe contains the empty set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∅ ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunr1om 10406 | A weak universe is infinite, because it contains all the finite levels of the cumulative hierarchy. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑅1 “ ω) ⊆ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunom 10407 | A weak universe contains all the finite ordinals, and hence is infinite. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ω ⊆ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunfi 10408 | A weak universe contains all finite sets with elements drawn from the universe. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ Fin) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunop 10409 | A weak universe is closed under ordered pairs. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunot 10410 | A weak universe is closed under ordered triples. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 〈𝐴, 𝐵, 𝐶〉 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunxp 10411 | A weak universe is closed under cartesian products. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunpm 10412 | A weak universe is closed under partial mappings. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunmap 10413 | A weak universe is closed under mappings. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunf 10414 | A weak universe is closed under functions with known domain and codomain. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wundm 10415 | A weak universe is closed under the domain operator. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → dom 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunrn 10416 | A weak universe is closed under the range operator. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ran 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wuncnv 10417 | A weak universe is closed under the converse operator. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ◡𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunres 10418 | A weak universe is closed under restrictions. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 ↾ 𝐵) ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunfv 10419 | A weak universe is closed under the function value operator. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴‘𝐵) ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wunco 10420 | A weak universe is closed under composition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 ∘ 𝐵) ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wuntpos 10421 | A weak universe is closed under transposition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → tpos 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | intwun 10422 | The intersection of a collection of weak universes is a weak universe. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ⊆ WUni ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) → ∩ 𝐴 ∈ WUni) | ||
Theorem | r1limwun 10423 | Each limit stage in the cumulative hierarchy is a weak universe. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ Lim 𝐴) → (𝑅1‘𝐴) ∈ WUni) | ||
Theorem | r1wunlim 10424 | The weak universes in the cumulative hierarchy are exactly the limit ordinals. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ((𝑅1‘𝐴) ∈ WUni ↔ Lim 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | wunex2 10425* | Construct a weak universe from a given set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (rec((𝑧 ∈ V ↦ ((𝑧 ∪ ∪ 𝑧) ∪ ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑧 ({𝒫 𝑥, ∪ 𝑥} ∪ ran (𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↦ {𝑥, 𝑦})))), (𝐴 ∪ 1o)) ↾ ω) & ⊢ 𝑈 = ∪ ran 𝐹 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝑈 ∈ WUni ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈)) | ||
Theorem | wunex 10426* | Construct a weak universe from a given set. See also wunex2 10425. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ∃𝑢 ∈ WUni 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑢) | ||
Theorem | uniwun 10427 | Every set is contained in a weak universe. This is the analogue of grothtsk 10522 for weak universes, but it is provable in ZF without the Tarski-Grothendieck axiom, contrary to grothtsk 10522. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ ∪ WUni = V | ||
Theorem | wunex3 10428 | Construct a weak universe from a given set. This version of wunex 10426 has a simpler proof, but requires the axiom of regularity. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = (𝑅1‘((rank‘𝐴) +o ω)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝑈 ∈ WUni ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈)) | ||
Theorem | wuncval 10429* | Value of the weak universe closure operator. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (wUniCl‘𝐴) = ∩ {𝑢 ∈ WUni ∣ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑢}) | ||
Theorem | wuncid 10430 | The weak universe closure of a set contains the set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐴 ⊆ (wUniCl‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | wunccl 10431 | The weak universe closure of a set is a weak universe. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (wUniCl‘𝐴) ∈ WUni) | ||
Theorem | wuncss 10432 | The weak universe closure is a subset of any other weak universe containing the set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ WUni ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈) → (wUniCl‘𝐴) ⊆ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | wuncidm 10433 | The weak universe closure is idempotent. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (wUniCl‘(wUniCl‘𝐴)) = (wUniCl‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | wuncval2 10434* | Our earlier expression for a containing weak universe is in fact the weak universe closure. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (rec((𝑧 ∈ V ↦ ((𝑧 ∪ ∪ 𝑧) ∪ ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑧 ({𝒫 𝑥, ∪ 𝑥} ∪ ran (𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↦ {𝑥, 𝑦})))), (𝐴 ∪ 1o)) ↾ ω) & ⊢ 𝑈 = ∪ ran 𝐹 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (wUniCl‘𝐴) = 𝑈) | ||
Syntax | ctsk 10435 | Extend class definition to include the class of all Tarski classes. |
class Tarski | ||
Definition | df-tsk 10436* | The class of all Tarski classes. Tarski classes is a phrase coined by Grzegorz Bancerek in his article Tarski's Classes and Ranks, Journal of Formalized Mathematics, Vol 1, No 3, May-August 1990. A Tarski class is a set whose existence is ensured by Tarski's axiom A (see ax-groth 10510 and the equivalent axioms). Axiom A was first presented in Tarski's article Ueber unerreichbare Kardinalzahlen. Tarski introduced the axiom A to enable ZFC to manage inaccessible cardinals. Later Grothendieck introduced the concept of Grothendieck universes and showed they were equal to transitive Tarski classes. (Contributed by FL, 30-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ Tarski = {𝑦 ∣ (∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 (𝒫 𝑧 ⊆ 𝑦 ∧ ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑦 𝒫 𝑧 ⊆ 𝑤) ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝒫 𝑦(𝑧 ≈ 𝑦 ∨ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦))} | ||
Theorem | eltskg 10437* | Properties of a Tarski class. (Contributed by FL, 30-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ (𝑇 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝑇 ∈ Tarski ↔ (∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑇 (𝒫 𝑧 ⊆ 𝑇 ∧ ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑇 𝒫 𝑧 ⊆ 𝑤) ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝒫 𝑇(𝑧 ≈ 𝑇 ∨ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑇)))) | ||
Theorem | eltsk2g 10438* | Properties of a Tarski class. (Contributed by FL, 30-Dec-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑇 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝑇 ∈ Tarski ↔ (∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑇 (𝒫 𝑧 ⊆ 𝑇 ∧ 𝒫 𝑧 ∈ 𝑇) ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝒫 𝑇(𝑧 ≈ 𝑇 ∨ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑇)))) | ||
Theorem | tskpwss 10439 | First axiom of a Tarski class. The subsets of an element of a Tarski class belong to the class. (Contributed by FL, 30-Dec-2010.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) → 𝒫 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskpw 10440 | Second axiom of a Tarski class. The powerset of an element of a Tarski class belongs to the class. (Contributed by FL, 30-Dec-2010.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) → 𝒫 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tsken 10441 | Third axiom of a Tarski class. A subset of a Tarski class is either equipotent to the class or an element of the class. (Contributed by FL, 30-Dec-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑇) → (𝐴 ≈ 𝑇 ∨ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇)) | ||
Theorem | 0tsk 10442 | The empty set is a (transitive) Tarski class. (Contributed by FL, 30-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ ∅ ∈ Tarski | ||
Theorem | tsksdom 10443 | An element of a Tarski class is strictly dominated by the class. JFM CLASSES2 th. 1. (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) → 𝐴 ≺ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskssel 10444 | A part of a Tarski class strictly dominated by the class is an element of the class. JFM CLASSES2 th. 2. (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑇 ∧ 𝐴 ≺ 𝑇) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskss 10445 | The subsets of an element of a Tarski class belong to the class. (Contributed by FL, 30-Dec-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskin 10446 | The intersection of two elements of a Tarski class belongs to the class. (Contributed by FL, 30-Dec-2010.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) → (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tsksn 10447 | A singleton of an element of a Tarski class belongs to the class. JFM CLASSES2 th. 2 (partly). (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) → {𝐴} ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tsktrss 10448 | A transitive element of a Tarski class is a part of the class. JFM CLASSES2 th. 8. (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ Tr 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tsksuc 10449 | If an element of a Tarski class is an ordinal number, its successor is an element of the class. JFM CLASSES2 th. 6 (partly). (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) → suc 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tsk0 10450 | A nonempty Tarski class contains the empty set. (Contributed by FL, 30-Dec-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝑇 ≠ ∅) → ∅ ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tsk1 10451 | One is an element of a nonempty Tarski class. (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝑇 ≠ ∅) → 1o ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tsk2 10452 | Two is an element of a nonempty Tarski class. (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝑇 ≠ ∅) → 2o ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | 2domtsk 10453 | If a Tarski class is not empty, it has more than two elements. (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝑇 ≠ ∅) → 2o ≺ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskr1om 10454 | A nonempty Tarski class is infinite, because it contains all the finite levels of the cumulative hierarchy. (This proof does not use ax-inf 9326.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝑇 ≠ ∅) → (𝑅1 “ ω) ⊆ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskr1om2 10455 | A nonempty Tarski class contains the whole finite cumulative hierarchy. (This proof does not use ax-inf 9326.) (Contributed by NM, 22-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝑇 ≠ ∅) → ∪ (𝑅1 “ ω) ⊆ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskinf 10456 | A nonempty Tarski class is infinite. (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝑇 ≠ ∅) → ω ≼ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskpr 10457 | If 𝐴 and 𝐵 are members of a Tarski class, their unordered pair is also an element of the class. JFM CLASSES2 th. 3 (partly). (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑇) → {𝐴, 𝐵} ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskop 10458 | If 𝐴 and 𝐵 are members of a Tarski class, their ordered pair is also an element of the class. JFM CLASSES2 th. 4. (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑇) → 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉 ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskxpss 10459 | A Cartesian product of two parts of a Tarski class is a part of the class. (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑇 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝑇) → (𝐴 × 𝐵) ⊆ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskwe2 10460 | A Tarski class is well-orderable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ (𝑇 ∈ Tarski → 𝑇 ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | inttsk 10461 | The intersection of a collection of Tarski classes is a Tarski class. (Contributed by FL, 17-Apr-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ⊆ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) → ∩ 𝐴 ∈ Tarski) | ||
Theorem | inar1 10462 | (𝑅1‘𝐴) for 𝐴 a strongly inaccessible cardinal is equipotent to 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Inacc → (𝑅1‘𝐴) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | r1omALT 10463 | Alternate proof of r1om 9931, shorter as a consequence of inar1 10462, but requiring AC. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-May-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑅1‘ω) ≈ ω | ||
Theorem | rankcf 10464 | Any set must be at least as large as the cofinality of its rank, because the ranks of the elements of 𝐴 form a cofinal map into (rank‘𝐴). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-May-2013.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝐴 ≺ (cf‘(rank‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | inatsk 10465 | (𝑅1‘𝐴) for 𝐴 a strongly inaccessible cardinal is a Tarski class. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 8-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Inacc → (𝑅1‘𝐴) ∈ Tarski) | ||
Theorem | r1omtsk 10466 | The set of hereditarily finite sets is a Tarski class. (The Tarski-Grothendieck Axiom is not needed for this theorem.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-May-2013.) |
⊢ (𝑅1‘ω) ∈ Tarski | ||
Theorem | tskord 10467 | A Tarski class contains all ordinals smaller than it. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 8-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐴 ≺ 𝑇) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskcard 10468 | An even more direct relationship than r1tskina 10469 to get an inaccessible cardinal out of a Tarski class: the size of any nonempty Tarski class is an inaccessible cardinal. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ 𝑇 ≠ ∅) → (card‘𝑇) ∈ Inacc) | ||
Theorem | r1tskina 10469 | There is a direct relationship between transitive Tarski classes and inaccessible cardinals: the Tarski classes that occur in the cumulative hierarchy are exactly at the strongly inaccessible cardinals. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 8-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → ((𝑅1‘𝐴) ∈ Tarski ↔ (𝐴 = ∅ ∨ 𝐴 ∈ Inacc))) | ||
Theorem | tskuni 10470 | The union of an element of a transitive Tarski class is in the set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ Tr 𝑇 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) → ∪ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskwun 10471 | A nonempty transitive Tarski class is a weak universe. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ Tr 𝑇 ∧ 𝑇 ≠ ∅) → 𝑇 ∈ WUni) | ||
Theorem | tskint 10472 | The intersection of an element of a transitive Tarski class is an element of the class. (Contributed by FL, 17-Apr-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ Tr 𝑇) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) → ∩ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskun 10473 | The union of two elements of a transitive Tarski class is in the set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ Tr 𝑇) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑇) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskxp 10474 | The Cartesian product of two elements of a transitive Tarski class is an element of the class. JFM CLASSES2 th. 67 (partly). (Contributed by FL, 15-Apr-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ Tr 𝑇) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑇) → (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskmap 10475 | Set exponentiation is an element of a transitive Tarski class. JFM CLASSES2 th. 67 (partly). (Contributed by FL, 15-Apr-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ Tr 𝑇) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑇) → (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | tskurn 10476 | A transitive Tarski class is closed under small unions. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ (((𝑇 ∈ Tarski ∧ Tr 𝑇) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑇 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶𝑇) → ∪ ran 𝐹 ∈ 𝑇) | ||
Syntax | cgru 10477 | Extend class notation to include the class of all Grothendieck universes. |
class Univ | ||
Definition | df-gru 10478* | A Grothendieck universe is a set that is closed with respect to all the operations that are common in set theory: pairs, powersets, unions, intersections, Cartesian products etc. Grothendieck and alii, Séminaire de Géométrie Algébrique 4, Exposé I, p. 185. It was designed to give a precise meaning to the concepts of categories of sets, groups... (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ Univ = {𝑢 ∣ (Tr 𝑢 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑢 (𝒫 𝑥 ∈ 𝑢 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑢 {𝑥, 𝑦} ∈ 𝑢 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ (𝑢 ↑m 𝑥)∪ ran 𝑦 ∈ 𝑢))} | ||
Theorem | elgrug 10479* | Properties of a Grothendieck universe. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ (𝑈 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝑈 ∈ Univ ↔ (Tr 𝑈 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑈 (𝒫 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑈 {𝑥, 𝑦} ∈ 𝑈 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ (𝑈 ↑m 𝑥)∪ ran 𝑦 ∈ 𝑈)))) | ||
Theorem | grutr 10480 | A Grothendieck universe is transitive. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝑈 ∈ Univ → Tr 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruelss 10481 | A Grothendieck universe is transitive, so each element is a subset of the universe. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | grupw 10482 | A Grothendieck universe contains the powerset of each of its members. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) → 𝒫 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruss 10483 | Any subset of an element of a Grothendieck universe is also an element. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | grupr 10484 | A Grothendieck universe contains pairs derived from its elements. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) → {𝐴, 𝐵} ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruurn 10485 | A Grothendieck universe contains the range of any function which takes values in the universe (see gruiun 10486 for a more intuitive version). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶𝑈) → ∪ ran 𝐹 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruiun 10486* | If 𝐵(𝑥) is a family of elements of 𝑈 and the index set 𝐴 is an element of 𝑈, then the indexed union ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴𝐵 is also an element of 𝑈, where 𝑈 is a Grothendieck universe. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) → ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruuni 10487 | A Grothendieck universe contains unions of its elements. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) → ∪ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | grurn 10488 | A Grothendieck universe contains the range of any function which takes values in the universe (see gruiun 10486 for a more intuitive version). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶𝑈) → ran 𝐹 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruima 10489 | A Grothendieck universe contains image sets drawn from its members. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ Fun 𝐹 ∧ (𝐹 “ 𝐴) ⊆ 𝑈) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 → (𝐹 “ 𝐴) ∈ 𝑈)) | ||
Theorem | gruel 10490 | Any element of an element of a Grothendieck universe is also an element of the universe. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | grusn 10491 | A Grothendieck universe contains the singletons of its elements. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) → {𝐴} ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruop 10492 | A Grothendieck universe contains ordered pairs of its elements. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) → 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruun 10493 | A Grothendieck universe contains binary unions of its elements. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruxp 10494 | A Grothendieck universe contains binary cartesian products of its elements. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) → (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | grumap 10495 | A Grothendieck universe contains all powers of its elements. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) → (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruixp 10496* | A Grothendieck universe contains indexed cartesian products of its elements. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruiin 10497* | A Grothendieck universe contains indexed intersections of its elements. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) → ∩ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruf 10498 | A Grothendieck universe contains all functions on its elements. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶𝑈) → 𝐹 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruen 10499 | A Grothendieck universe contains all subsets of itself that are equipotent to an element of the universe. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐵 ≈ 𝐴)) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | gruwun 10500 | A nonempty Grothendieck universe is a weak universe. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝑈 ∈ Univ ∧ 𝑈 ≠ ∅) → 𝑈 ∈ WUni) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |