Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 20 of 466) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29280) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29281-30803) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30804-46521) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | nf3and 1901 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder nf3an 1904. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | nfan 1902 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, then it is not free in (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-Jan-2018.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 9-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfnan 1903 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, then it is not free in (𝜑 ⊼ 𝜓). (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 2-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ⊼ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nf3an 1904 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, 𝜓, and 𝜒, then it is not free in (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜒 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | nfbid 1905 | If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, then it is not free in (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 29-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | nfbi 1906 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, then it is not free in (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfor 1907 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, then it is not free in (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nf3or 1908 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, 𝜓, and 𝜒, then it is not free in (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓 ∨ 𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜒 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓 ∨ 𝜒) | ||
This database develops mathematics from first-order logic, which has only nonempty models. Before stating axioms excluding the empty model (typically, ax-6 1971 in logic and ax-nul 5230 in set theory), we state in this short subsection a few results relative to the empty domain, which we characterize by the assumption ¬ ∃𝑥⊤. As expected, on the empty domain, every universally quantified formula is true (emptyal 1911) and every existential formula is false (emptyex 1910), and every variable is effectively nonfree in any formula (emptynf 1912). | ||
Theorem | empty 1909 | Two characterizations of the empty domain. (Contributed by Gérard Lang, 5-Feb-2024.) |
⊢ (¬ ∃𝑥⊤ ↔ ∀𝑥⊥) | ||
Theorem | emptyex 1910 | On the empty domain, any existentially quantified formula is false. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 21-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ (¬ ∃𝑥⊤ → ¬ ∃𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | emptyal 1911 | On the empty domain, any universally quantified formula is true. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 12-Mar-2023.) |
⊢ (¬ ∃𝑥⊤ → ∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | emptynf 1912 | On the empty domain, any variable is effectively nonfree in any formula. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 12-Mar-2023.) |
⊢ (¬ ∃𝑥⊤ → Ⅎ𝑥𝜑) | ||
Axiom | ax-5 1913* |
Axiom of Distinctness. This axiom quantifies a variable over a formula
in which it does not occur. Axiom C5 in [Megill] p. 444 (p. 11 of the
preprint). Also appears as Axiom B6 (p. 75) of system S2 of [Tarski]
p. 77 and Axiom C5-1 of [Monk2] p. 113.
(See comments in ax5ALT 36921 about the logical redundancy of ax-5 1913 in the presence of our obsolete axioms.) This axiom essentially says that if 𝑥 does not occur in 𝜑, i.e. 𝜑 does not depend on 𝑥 in any way, then we can add the quantifier ∀𝑥 to 𝜑 with no further assumptions. By sp 2176, we can also remove the quantifier (unconditionally). For an explanation of disjoint variable conditions, see https://us.metamath.org/mpeuni/mmset.html#distinct 2176. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jan-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | ax5d 1914* | Version of ax-5 1913 with antecedent. Useful in proofs of deduction versions of bound-variable hypothesis builders. (Contributed by NM, 1-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | ax5e 1915* | A rephrasing of ax-5 1913 using the existential quantifier. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 4-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | ax5ea 1916* | If a formula holds for some value of a variable not occurring in it, then it holds for all values of that variable. (Contributed by BJ, 28-Dec-2020.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfv 1917* | If 𝑥 is not present in 𝜑, then 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) Definition change. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 12-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | nfvd 1918* | nfv 1917 with antecedent. Useful in proofs of deduction versions of bound-variable hypothesis builders such as nfimd 1897. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | alimdv 1919* | Deduction form of Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90, see alim 1813. See alimdh 1820 and alimd 2205 for versions without a distinct variable condition. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | eximdv 1920* | Deduction form of Theorem 19.22 of [Margaris] p. 90, see exim 1836. See eximdh 1867 and eximd 2209 for versions without a distinct variable condition. (Contributed by NM, 27-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜓 → ∃𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | 2alimdv 1921* | Deduction form of Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90 with two quantifiers, see alim 1813. (Contributed by NM, 27-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜓 → ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | 2eximdv 1922* | Deduction form of Theorem 19.22 of [Margaris] p. 90 with two quantifiers, see exim 1836. (Contributed by NM, 3-Aug-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜓 → ∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | albidv 1923* | Formula-building rule for universal quantifier (deduction form). See also albidh 1869 and albid 2215. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | exbidv 1924* | Formula-building rule for existential quantifier (deduction form). See also exbidh 1870 and exbid 2216. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∃𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | nfbidv 1925* | An equality theorem for nonfreeness. See nfbidf 2217 for a version without disjoint variable condition but requiring more axioms. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) Remove dependency on ax-6 1971, ax-7 2011, ax-12 2171 by adapting proof of nfbidf 2217. (Revised by BJ, 25-Sep-2022.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ↔ Ⅎ𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | 2albidv 1926* | Formula-building rule for two universal quantifiers (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 4-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | 2exbidv 1927* | Formula-building rule for two existential quantifiers (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 1-May-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜓 ↔ ∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | 3exbidv 1928* | Formula-building rule for three existential quantifiers (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 1-May-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧𝜓 ↔ ∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | 4exbidv 1929* | Formula-building rule for four existential quantifiers (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 3-Aug-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧∃𝑤𝜓 ↔ ∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧∃𝑤𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | alrimiv 1930* | Inference form of Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. See 19.21 2200 and 19.21v 1942. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | alrimivv 1931* | Inference form of Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. See 19.21 2200 and 19.21v 1942. (Contributed by NM, 31-Jul-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜓) | ||
Theorem | alrimdv 1932* | Deduction form of Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. See 19.21 2200 and 19.21v 1942. (Contributed by NM, 10-Feb-1997.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | exlimiv 1933* |
Inference form of Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris]
p. 90, see 19.23 2204.
See exlimi 2210 for a more general version requiring more axioms. This inference, along with its many variants such as rexlimdv 3212, is used to implement a metatheorem called "Rule C" that is given in many logic textbooks. See, for example, Rule C in [Mendelson] p. 81, Rule C in [Margaris] p. 40, or Rule C in Hirst and Hirst's A Primer for Logic and Proof p. 59 (PDF p. 65) at http://www.appstate.edu/~hirstjl/primer/hirst.pdf 3212. In informal proofs, the statement "Let 𝐶 be an element such that..." almost always means an implicit application of Rule C. In essence, Rule C states that if we can prove that some element 𝑥 exists satisfying a wff, i.e. ∃𝑥𝜑(𝑥) where 𝜑(𝑥) has 𝑥 free, then we can use 𝜑(𝐶) as a hypothesis for the proof where 𝐶 is a new (fictitious) constant not appearing previously in the proof, nor in any axioms used, nor in the theorem to be proved. The purpose of Rule C is to get rid of the existential quantifier. We cannot do this in Metamath directly. Instead, we use the original 𝜑 (containing 𝑥) as an antecedent for the main part of the proof. We eventually arrive at (𝜑 → 𝜓) where 𝜓 is the theorem to be proved and does not contain 𝑥. Then we apply exlimiv 1933 to arrive at (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓). Finally, we separately prove ∃𝑥𝜑 and detach it with modus ponens ax-mp 5 to arrive at the final theorem 𝜓, see exlimiiv 1934. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) Remove dependencies on ax-6 1971 and ax-8 2108. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 4-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | exlimiiv 1934* | Inference (Rule C) associated with exlimiv 1933. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Dec-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ ∃𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | exlimivv 1935* | Inference form of Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90, see 19.23 2204. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | exlimdv 1936* | Deduction form of Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90, see 19.23 2204. (Contributed by NM, 27-Apr-1994.) Remove dependencies on ax-6 1971, ax-7 2011. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 4-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | exlimdvv 1937* | Deduction form of Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90, see 19.23 2204. (Contributed by NM, 31-Jul-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | exlimddv 1938* | Existential elimination rule of natural deduction (Rule C, explained in exlimiv 1933). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | nexdv 1939* | Deduction for generalization rule for negated wff. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) Reduce dependencies on axioms. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 13-Jul-2020.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ ∃𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 2ax5 1940* | Quantification of two variables over a formula in which they do not occur. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 12-Apr-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑) | ||
Theorem | stdpc5v 1941* | Version of stdpc5 2201 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by BJ, 7-Mar-2020.) Revised to shorten 19.21v 1942. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 12-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.21v 1942* |
Version of 19.21 2200 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring
fewer
axioms.
Notational convention: We sometimes suffix with "v" the label of a theorem using a distinct variable ("dv") condition instead of a nonfreeness hypothesis such as Ⅎ𝑥𝜑. Conversely, we sometimes suffix with "f" the label of a theorem introducing such a nonfreeness hypothesis ("f" stands for "not free in", see df-nf 1787) instead of a disjoint variable condition. For instance, 19.21v 1942 versus 19.21 2200 and vtoclf 3497 versus vtocl 3498. Note that "not free in" is less restrictive than "does not occur in". Note that the version with a disjoint variable condition is easily proved from the version with the corresponding nonfreeness hypothesis, by using nfv 1917. However, the dv version can often be proved from fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) Reduce dependencies on axioms. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2020.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.32v 1943* | Version of 19.32 2226 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by BJ, 7-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∨ ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.31v 1944* | Version of 19.31 2227 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by BJ, 7-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∨ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.23v 1945* | Version of 19.23 2204 with a disjoint variable condition instead of a nonfreeness hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 28-Jun-1998.) Reduce dependencies on axioms. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 11-Jan-2020.) Remove dependency on ax-6 1971. (Revised by Rohan Ridenour, 15-Apr-2022.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.23vv 1946* | Theorem 19.23v 1945 extended to two variables. (Contributed by NM, 10-Aug-2004.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | pm11.53v 1947* | Version of pm11.53 2344 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by BJ, 7-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.36imv 1948* | One direction of 19.36v 1991 that can be proven without ax-6 1971. (Contributed by Rohan Ridenour, 16-Apr-2022.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 22-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.36imvOLD 1949* | Obsolete version of 19.36imv 1948 as of 22-Sep-2024. (Contributed by Rohan Ridenour, 16-Apr-2022.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.36iv 1950* | Inference associated with 19.36v 1991. Version of 19.36i 2224 with a disjoint variable condition. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) Reduce dependencies on axioms. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 17-Jan-2020.) Remove dependency on ax-6 1971. (Revised by Rohan Ridenour, 15-Apr-2022.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 19.37imv 1951* | One direction of 19.37v 1995 that can be proven without ax-6 1971. (Contributed by Rohan Ridenour, 16-Apr-2022.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.37iv 1952* | Inference associated with 19.37v 1995. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) Remove dependency on ax-6 1971. (Revised by Rohan Ridenour, 15-Apr-2022.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 19.41v 1953* | Version of 19.41 2228 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) Remove dependency on ax-6 1971. (Revised by Rohan Ridenour, 15-Apr-2022.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.41vv 1954* | Version of 19.41 2228 with two quantifiers and a disjoint variable condition requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 30-Apr-1995.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.41vvv 1955* | Version of 19.41 2228 with three quantifiers and a disjoint variable condition requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 30-Apr-1995.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.41vvvv 1956* | Version of 19.41 2228 with four quantifiers and a disjoint variable condition requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by FL, 14-Jul-2007.) |
⊢ (∃𝑤∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑤∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.42v 1957* | Version of 19.42 2229 with a disjoint variable condition requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | exdistr 1958* | Distribution of existential quantifiers. See also exdistrv 1959. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ ∃𝑥(𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | exdistrv 1959* | Distribute a pair of existential quantifiers (over disjoint variables) over a conjunction. Combination of 19.41v 1953 and 19.42v 1957. For a version with fewer disjoint variable conditions but requiring more axioms, see eeanv 2347. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Sep-2022.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 4exdistrv 1960* | Distribute two pairs of existential quantifiers (over disjoint variables) over a conjunction. For a version with fewer disjoint variable conditions but requiring more axioms, see ee4anv 2349. (Contributed by BJ, 5-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑧∃𝑦∃𝑤(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.42vv 1961* | Version of 19.42 2229 with two quantifiers and a disjoint variable condition requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 16-Mar-1995.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | exdistr2 1962* | Distribution of existential quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 17-Mar-1995.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ ∃𝑥(𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑦∃𝑧𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.42vvv 1963* | Version of 19.42 2229 with three quantifiers and a disjoint variable condition requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 21-Sep-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 27-Aug-2023.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 3exdistr 1964* | Distribution of existential quantifiers in a triple conjunction. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) ↔ ∃𝑥(𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑦(𝜓 ∧ ∃𝑧𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | 4exdistr 1965* | Distribution of existential quantifiers in a quadruple conjunction. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 20-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧∃𝑤((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜃)) ↔ ∃𝑥(𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑦(𝜓 ∧ ∃𝑧(𝜒 ∧ ∃𝑤𝜃)))) | ||
The equality predicate was introduced above in wceq 1539 for use by df-tru 1542. See the comments in that section. In this section, we continue with its first "real" use. | ||
Theorem | weq 1966 |
Extend wff definition to include atomic formulas using the equality
predicate.
(Instead of introducing weq 1966 as an axiomatic statement, as was done in an older version of this database, we introduce it by "proving" a special case of set theory's more general wceq 1539. This lets us avoid overloading the = connective, thus preventing ambiguity that would complicate certain Metamath parsers. However, logically weq 1966 is considered to be a primitive syntax, even though here it is artificially "derived" from wceq 1539. Note: To see the proof steps of this syntax proof, type "MM> SHOW PROOF weq / ALL" in the Metamath program.) (Contributed by NM, 24-Jan-2006.) |
wff 𝑥 = 𝑦 | ||
Theorem | speimfw 1967 | Specialization, with additional weakening (compared to 19.2 1980) to allow bundling of 𝑥 and 𝑦. Uses only Tarski's FOL axiom schemes. (Contributed by NM, 23-Apr-2017.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 5-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | speimfwALT 1968 | Alternate proof of speimfw 1967 (longer compressed proof, but fewer essential steps). (Contributed by NM, 23-Apr-2017.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 5-Aug-2017.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | spimfw 1969 | Specialization, with additional weakening (compared to sp 2176) to allow bundling of 𝑥 and 𝑦. Uses only Tarski's FOL axiom schemes. (Contributed by NM, 23-Apr-2017.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 7-Aug-2017.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜓 → ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | ax12i 1970 | Inference that has ax-12 2171 (without ∀𝑦) as its conclusion. Uses only Tarski's FOL axiom schemes. The hypotheses may be eliminable without using ax-12 2171 in special cases. Proof similar to Lemma 16 of [Tarski] p. 70. (Contributed by NM, 20-May-2008.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑))) | ||
Axiom | ax-6 1971 |
Axiom of Existence. One of the equality and substitution axioms of
predicate calculus with equality. This axiom tells us that at least one
thing exists. In this form (not requiring that 𝑥 and 𝑦 be
distinct) it was used in an axiom system of Tarski (see Axiom B7' in
footnote 1 of [KalishMontague] p.
81.) It is equivalent to axiom scheme
C10' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the
preprint); the equivalence is
established by axc10 2385 and ax6fromc10 36910. A more convenient form of this
axiom is ax6e 2383, which has additional remarks.
Raph Levien proved the independence of this axiom from the other logical axioms on 12-Apr-2005. See item 16 at https://us.metamath.org/award2003.html 2383. ax-6 1971 can be proved from the weaker version ax6v 1972 requiring that the variables be distinct; see Theorem ax6 2384. ax-6 1971 can also be proved from the Axiom of Separation (in the form that we use that axiom, where free variables are not universally quantified). See Theorem ax6vsep 5227. Except by ax6v 1972, this axiom should not be referenced directly. Instead, use Theorem ax6 2384. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jan-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 | ||
Theorem | ax6v 1972* |
Axiom B7 of [Tarski] p. 75, which requires that
𝑥
and 𝑦 be
distinct. This trivial proof is intended merely to weaken Axiom ax-6 1971
by adding a distinct variable restriction ($d). From here on, ax-6 1971
should not be referenced directly by any other proof, so that Theorem
ax6 2384 will show that we can recover ax-6 1971
from this weaker version if
it were an axiom (as it is in the case of Tarski).
Note: Introducing 𝑥, 𝑦 as a distinct variable group "out of the blue" with no apparent justification has puzzled some people, but it is perfectly sound. All we are doing is adding an additional prerequisite, similar to adding an unnecessary logical hypothesis, that results in a weakening of the theorem. This means that any future theorem that references ax6v 1972 must have a $d specified for the two variables that get substituted for 𝑥 and 𝑦. The $d does not propagate "backwards", i.e., it does not impose a requirement on ax-6 1971. When possible, use of this theorem rather than ax6 2384 is preferred since its derivation is much shorter and requires fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 | ||
Theorem | ax6ev 1973* | At least one individual exists. Weaker version of ax6e 2383. When possible, use of this theorem rather than ax6e 2383 is preferred since its derivation is much shorter and requires fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 3-Aug-2017.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 | ||
Theorem | spimw 1974* | Specialization. Lemma 8 of [KalishMontague] p. 87. Uses only Tarski's FOL axiom schemes. (Contributed by NM, 19-Apr-2017.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 7-Aug-2017.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜓 → ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | spimew 1975* | Existential introduction, using implicit substitution. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 22-Oct-2023.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | speiv 1976* | Inference from existential specialization. (Contributed by NM, 19-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 22-Oct-2023.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓 → 𝜑)) & ⊢ 𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | speivw 1977* | Version of spei 2394 with a disjoint variable condition, which does not require ax-13 2372 (neither ax-7 2011 nor ax-12 2171). (Contributed by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | exgen 1978 | Rule of existential generalization, similar to universal generalization ax-gen 1798, but valid only if an individual exists. Its proof requires ax-6 1971 in our axiomatization but the equality predicate does not occur in its statement. Some fundamental theorems of predicate calculus can be proven from ax-gen 1798, ax-4 1812 and this theorem alone, not requiring ax-7 2011 or excessive distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 12-Nov-2017.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 20-Oct-2023.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | extru 1979 | There exists a variable such that ⊤ holds; that is, there exists a variable. This corresponds under the standard translation to one of the formulations of the modal axiom (D), the other being 19.2 1980. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 13-Sep-2011.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 12-May-2019.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥⊤ | ||
Theorem | 19.2 1980 | Theorem 19.2 of [Margaris] p. 89. This corresponds to the axiom (D) of modal logic (the other standard formulation being extru 1979). Note: This proof is very different from Margaris' because we only have Tarski's FOL axiom schemes available at this point. See the later 19.2g 2181 for a more conventional proof of a more general result, which uses additional axioms. The reverse implication is the defining property of effective nonfreeness (see df-nf 1787). (Contributed by NM, 2-Aug-2017.) Remove dependency on ax-7 2011. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 4-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 19.2d 1981 | Deduction associated with 19.2 1980. (Contributed by BJ, 12-May-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 19.8w 1982 | Weak version of 19.8a 2174 and instance of 19.2d 1981. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-2017.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 4-Dec-2017.) (Revised by BJ, 31-Mar-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | spnfw 1983 | Weak version of sp 2176. Uses only Tarski's FOL axiom schemes. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-2017.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-Aug-2017.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | spvw 1984* | Version of sp 2176 when 𝑥 does not occur in 𝜑. Converse of ax-5 1913. Uses only Tarski's FOL axiom schemes. (Contributed by NM, 10-Apr-2017.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 4-Dec-2017.) Shorten 19.3v 1985. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 20-Oct-2023.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 19.3v 1985* | Version of 19.3 2195 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. Any formula can be universally quantified using a variable which it does not contain. See also 19.9v 1987. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 13-Sep-2011.) Remove dependency on ax-7 2011. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 4-Dec-2017.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 20-Oct-2023.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 19.8v 1986* | Version of 19.8a 2174 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. Converse of ax5e 1915. (Contributed by BJ, 12-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 19.9v 1987* | Version of 19.9 2198 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. Any formula can be existentially quantified using a variable which it does not contain. See also 19.3v 1985. (Contributed by NM, 28-May-1995.) Remove dependency on ax-7 2011. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 4-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 ↔ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 19.39 1988 | Theorem 19.39 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
⊢ ((∃𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓) → ∃𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.24 1989 | Theorem 19.24 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → ∃𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.34 1990 | Theorem 19.34 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥𝜑 ∨ ∃𝑥𝜓) → ∃𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.36v 1991* | Version of 19.36 2223 with a disjoint variable condition instead of a nonfreeness hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1993.) Reduce dependencies on axioms. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 17-Jan-2020.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.12vvv 1992* | Version of 19.12vv 2345 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. See also 19.12 2321. (Contributed by BJ, 18-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ ∀𝑦∃𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.27v 1993* | Version of 19.27 2220 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jun-2004.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.28v 1994* | Version of 19.28 2221 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.37v 1995* | Version of 19.37 2225 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.44v 1996* | Version of 19.44 2230 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑 ∨ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.45v 1997* | Version of 19.45 2231 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∨ ∃𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | spimevw 1998* | Existential introduction, using implicit substitution. This is to spimew 1975 what spimvw 1999 is to spimw 1974. Version of spimev 2392 and spimefv 2191 with an additional disjoint variable condition, using only Tarski's FOL axiom schemes. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jan-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 17-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | spimvw 1999* | A weak form of specialization. Lemma 8 of [KalishMontague] p. 87. Uses only Tarski's FOL axiom schemes. For stronger forms using more axioms, see spimv 2390 and spimfv 2232. (Contributed by NM, 9-Apr-2017.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | spvv 2000* | Specialization, using implicit substitution. Version of spv 2393 with a disjoint variable condition, which does not require ax-7 2011, ax-12 2171, ax-13 2372. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |