Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 88 of 466) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29289) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29290-30812) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30813-46532) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | elixp 8701* | Membership in an infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ 𝐹 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↔ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐹‘𝑥) ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | elixpconst 8702* | Membership in an infinite Cartesian product of a constant 𝐵. (Contributed by NM, 12-Apr-2008.) |
⊢ 𝐹 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↔ 𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵) | ||
Theorem | ixpconstg 8703* | Infinite Cartesian product of a constant 𝐵. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = (𝐵 ↑m 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ixpconst 8704* | Infinite Cartesian product of a constant 𝐵. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = (𝐵 ↑m 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ixpeq1 8705* | Equality theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 29-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpeq1d 8706* | Equality theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ss2ixp 8707 | Subclass theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 29-Sep-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐶 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ⊆ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpeq2 8708 | Equality theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 29-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = 𝐶 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpeq2dva 8709* | Equality theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpeq2dv 8710* | Equality theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | cbvixp 8711* | Change bound variable in an indexed Cartesian product. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 20-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐵 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐶 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = X𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 | ||
Theorem | cbvixpv 8712* | Change bound variable in an indexed Cartesian product. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = X𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 | ||
Theorem | nfixpw 8713* | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for indexed Cartesian product. Version of nfixp 8714 with a disjoint variable condition, which does not require ax-13 2373. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Gino Giotto, 26-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 | ||
Theorem | nfixp 8714 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for indexed Cartesian product. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2373. Use the weaker nfixpw 8713 when possible. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 | ||
Theorem | nfixp1 8715 | The index variable in an indexed Cartesian product is not free. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 19-Jun-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 | ||
Theorem | ixpprc 8716* | A cartesian product of proper-class many sets is empty, because any function in the cartesian product has to be a set with domain 𝐴, which is not possible for a proper class domain. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 25-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝐴 ∈ V → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = ∅) | ||
Theorem | ixpf 8717* | A member of an infinite Cartesian product maps to the indexed union of the product argument. Remark in [Enderton] p. 54. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 → 𝐹:𝐴⟶∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | uniixp 8718* | The union of an infinite Cartesian product is included in a Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ∪ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ⊆ (𝐴 × ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | ixpexg 8719* | The existence of an infinite Cartesian product. 𝑥 is normally a free-variable parameter in 𝐵. Remark in Enderton p. 54. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 25-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | ixpin 8720* | The intersection of two infinite Cartesian products. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐵 ∩ 𝐶) = (X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∩ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpiin 8721* | The indexed intersection of a collection of infinite Cartesian products. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ≠ ∅ → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∩ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶 = ∩ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpint 8722* | The intersection of a collection of infinite Cartesian products. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ≠ ∅ → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∩ 𝐵 = ∩ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑦) | ||
Theorem | ixp0x 8723 | An infinite Cartesian product with an empty index set. (Contributed by NM, 21-Sep-2007.) |
⊢ X𝑥 ∈ ∅ 𝐴 = {∅} | ||
Theorem | ixpssmap2g 8724* | An infinite Cartesian product is a subset of set exponentiation. This version of ixpssmapg 8725 avoids ax-rep 5210. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ⊆ (∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↑m 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ixpssmapg 8725* | An infinite Cartesian product is a subset of set exponentiation. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 19-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ⊆ (∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↑m 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | 0elixp 8726 | Membership of the empty set in an infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by Steve Rodriguez, 29-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ ∅ ∈ X𝑥 ∈ ∅ 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | ixpn0 8727 | The infinite Cartesian product of a family 𝐵(𝑥) with an empty member is empty. The converse of this theorem is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice, see ac9 10248. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ≠ ∅ → ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ≠ ∅) | ||
Theorem | ixp0 8728 | The infinite Cartesian product of a family 𝐵(𝑥) with an empty member is empty. The converse of this theorem is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice, see ac9 10248. (Contributed by NM, 1-Oct-2006.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = ∅ → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = ∅) | ||
Theorem | ixpssmap 8729* | An infinite Cartesian product is a subset of set exponentiation. Remark in [Enderton] p. 54. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ⊆ (∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↑m 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | resixp 8730* | Restriction of an element of an infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by FL, 7-Nov-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 31-May-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) → (𝐹 ↾ 𝐵) ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | undifixp 8731* | Union of two projections of a cartesian product. (Contributed by FL, 7-Nov-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶 ∧ 𝐺 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 ∖ 𝐵)𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) → (𝐹 ∪ 𝐺) ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | mptelixpg 8732* | Condition for an explicit member of an indexed product. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 4-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐼 ∈ 𝑉 → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 ↦ 𝐽) ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 𝐾 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 𝐽 ∈ 𝐾)) | ||
Theorem | resixpfo 8733* | Restriction of elements of an infinite Cartesian product creates a surjection, if the original Cartesian product is nonempty. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑓 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 ↦ (𝑓 ↾ 𝐵)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 ≠ ∅) → 𝐹:X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶–onto→X𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | elixpsn 8734* | Membership in a class of singleton functions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ {𝐴}𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝐹 = {〈𝐴, 𝑦〉})) | ||
Theorem | ixpsnf1o 8735* | A bijection between a class and single-point functions to it. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ ({𝐼} × {𝑥})) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐼 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→X𝑦 ∈ {𝐼}𝐴) | ||
Theorem | mapsnf1o 8736* | A bijection between a set and single-point functions to it. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ ({𝐼} × {𝑥})) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐼 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→(𝐴 ↑m {𝐼})) | ||
Theorem | boxriin 8737* | A rectangular subset of a rectangular set can be recovered as the relative intersection of single-axis restrictions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 𝐴 = (X𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 𝐵 ∩ ∩ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐼 X𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 if(𝑥 = 𝑦, 𝐴, 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | boxcutc 8738* | The relative complement of a box set restricted on one axis. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 ⊆ 𝐵) → (X𝑘 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∖ X𝑘 ∈ 𝐴 if(𝑘 = 𝑋, 𝐶, 𝐵)) = X𝑘 ∈ 𝐴 if(𝑘 = 𝑋, (𝐵 ∖ 𝐶), 𝐵)) | ||
Syntax | cen 8739 | Extend class definition to include the equinumerosity relation ("approximately equals" symbol) |
class ≈ | ||
Syntax | cdom 8740 | Extend class definition to include the dominance relation (curly "less than or equal to") |
class ≼ | ||
Syntax | csdm 8741 | Extend class definition to include the strict dominance relation (curly less-than) |
class ≺ | ||
Syntax | cfn 8742 | Extend class definition to include the class of all finite sets. |
class Fin | ||
Definition | df-en 8743* | Define the equinumerosity relation. Definition of [Enderton] p. 129. We define ≈ to be a binary relation rather than a connective, so its arguments must be sets to be meaningful. This is acceptable because we do not consider equinumerosity for proper classes. We derive the usual definition as bren 8752. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ ≈ = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝑥–1-1-onto→𝑦} | ||
Definition | df-dom 8744* | Define the dominance relation. For an alternate definition see dfdom2 8775. Compare Definition of [Enderton] p. 145. Typical textbook definitions are derived as brdom 8759 and domen 8760. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ ≼ = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝑥–1-1→𝑦} | ||
Definition | df-sdom 8745 | Define the strict dominance relation. Alternate possible definitions are derived as brsdom 8772 and brsdom2 8893. Definition 3 of [Suppes] p. 97. (Contributed by NM, 31-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ ≺ = ( ≼ ∖ ≈ ) | ||
Definition | df-fin 8746* | Define the (proper) class of all finite sets. Similar to Definition 10.29 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 91, whose "Fin(a)" corresponds to our "𝑎 ∈ Fin". This definition is meaningful whether or not we accept the Axiom of Infinity ax-inf2 9408. If we accept Infinity, we can also express 𝐴 ∈ Fin by 𝐴 ≺ ω (Theorem isfinite 9419.) (Contributed by NM, 22-Aug-2008.) |
⊢ Fin = {𝑥 ∣ ∃𝑦 ∈ ω 𝑥 ≈ 𝑦} | ||
Theorem | relen 8747 | Equinumerosity is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ Rel ≈ | ||
Theorem | reldom 8748 | Dominance is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ Rel ≼ | ||
Theorem | relsdom 8749 | Strict dominance is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 31-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ Rel ≺ | ||
Theorem | encv 8750 | If two classes are equinumerous, both classes are sets. (Contributed by AV, 21-Mar-2019.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 → (𝐴 ∈ V ∧ 𝐵 ∈ V)) | ||
Theorem | breng 8751* | Equinumerosity relation. This variation of bren 8752 does not require the Axiom of Union. (Contributed by BTernaryTau, 23-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | bren 8752* | Equinumerosity relation. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jun-1998.) (Proof shortened by BTernaryTau, 23-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵) | ||
Theorem | brenOLD 8753* | Obsolete version of bren 8752 as of 23-Sep-2024. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jun-1998.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵) | ||
Theorem | brdom2g 8754* | Dominance relation. This variation of brdomg 8755 does not require the Axiom of Union. (Contributed by BTernaryTau, 29-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1→𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | brdomg 8755* | Dominance relation. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jun-1998.) (Proof shortened by BTernaryTau, 29-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1→𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | brdomgOLD 8756* | Obsolete version of brdomg 8755 as of 29-Nov-2024. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jun-1998.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1→𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | brdomi 8757* | Dominance relation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) Avoid ax-un 7597. (Revised by BTernaryTau, 29-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 → ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1→𝐵) | ||
Theorem | brdomiOLD 8758* | Obsolete version of brdomi 8757 as of 29-Nov-2024. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 → ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1→𝐵) | ||
Theorem | brdom 8759* | Dominance relation. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jun-1998.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1→𝐵) | ||
Theorem | domen 8760* | Dominance in terms of equinumerosity. Example 1 of [Enderton] p. 146. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jun-1998.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝐴 ≈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑥 ⊆ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | domeng 8761* | Dominance in terms of equinumerosity, with the sethood requirement expressed as an antecedent. Example 1 of [Enderton] p. 146. (Contributed by NM, 24-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝐴 ≈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑥 ⊆ 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | ctex 8762 | A countable set is a set. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 29-Dec-2016.) (Proof shortened by Jim Kingdon, 13-Mar-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≼ ω → 𝐴 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | f1oen3g 8763 | The domain and range of a one-to-one, onto set function are equinumerous. This variation of f1oeng 8768 does not require the Axiom of Replacement nor the Axiom of Power Sets. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 10-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵) → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | f1dom3g 8764 | The domain of a one-to-one set function is dominated by its codomain when the latter is a set. This variation of f1domg 8769 does not require the Axiom of Replacement nor the Axiom of Power Sets. (Contributed by BTernaryTau, 9-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵) → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | f1oen2g 8765 | The domain and range of a one-to-one, onto function are equinumerous. This variation of f1oeng 8768 does not require the Axiom of Replacement. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵) → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | f1dom2g 8766 | The domain of a one-to-one function is dominated by its codomain. This variation of f1domg 8769 does not require the Axiom of Replacement. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) (Proof shortened by BTernaryTau, 25-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵) → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | f1dom2gOLD 8767 | Obsolete version of f1dom2g 8766 as of 25-Sep-2024. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵) → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | f1oeng 8768 | The domain and range of a one-to-one, onto function are equinumerous. (Contributed by NM, 19-Jun-1998.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵) → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | f1domg 8769 | The domain of a one-to-one function is dominated by its codomain. (Contributed by NM, 4-Sep-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 → (𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | f1oen 8770 | The domain and range of a one-to-one, onto function are equinumerous. (Contributed by NM, 19-Jun-1998.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵 → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | f1dom 8771 | The domain of a one-to-one function is dominated by its codomain. (Contributed by NM, 19-Jun-1998.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | brsdom 8772 | Strict dominance relation, meaning "𝐵 is strictly greater in size than 𝐴". Definition of [Mendelson] p. 255. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jun-1998.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≺ 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∧ ¬ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | isfi 8773* | Express "𝐴 is finite". Definition 10.29 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 91 (whose "Fin " is a predicate instead of a class). (Contributed by NM, 22-Aug-2008.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Fin ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ ω 𝐴 ≈ 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | enssdom 8774 | Equinumerosity implies dominance. (Contributed by NM, 31-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ ≈ ⊆ ≼ | ||
Theorem | dfdom2 8775 | Alternate definition of dominance. (Contributed by NM, 17-Jun-1998.) |
⊢ ≼ = ( ≺ ∪ ≈ ) | ||
Theorem | endom 8776 | Equinumerosity implies dominance. Theorem 15 of [Suppes] p. 94. (Contributed by NM, 28-May-1998.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | sdomdom 8777 | Strict dominance implies dominance. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jun-1998.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≺ 𝐵 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | sdomnen 8778 | Strict dominance implies non-equinumerosity. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jun-1998.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≺ 𝐵 → ¬ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | brdom2 8779 | Dominance in terms of strict dominance and equinumerosity. Theorem 22(iv) of [Suppes] p. 97. (Contributed by NM, 17-Jun-1998.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ≺ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | bren2 8780 | Equinumerosity expressed in terms of dominance and strict dominance. (Contributed by NM, 23-Oct-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∧ ¬ 𝐴 ≺ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | enrefg 8781 | Equinumerosity is reflexive. Theorem 1 of [Suppes] p. 92. (Contributed by NM, 18-Jun-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | enref 8782 | Equinumerosity is reflexive. Theorem 1 of [Suppes] p. 92. (Contributed by NM, 25-Sep-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | eqeng 8783 | Equality implies equinumerosity. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 = 𝐵 → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | domrefg 8784 | Dominance is reflexive. (Contributed by NM, 18-Jun-1998.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | en2d 8785* | Equinumerosity inference from an implicit one-to-one onto function. (Contributed by NM, 27-Jul-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-May-2014.) (Revised by AV, 4-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝐷 ∈ 𝑌)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐶) ↔ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐷))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | en3d 8786* | Equinumerosity inference from an implicit one-to-one onto function. (Contributed by NM, 27-Jul-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-May-2014.) (Revised by AV, 4-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝐷 ∈ 𝐴)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝑥 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑦 = 𝐶))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | en2i 8787* | Equinumerosity inference from an implicit one-to-one onto function. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝐷 ∈ V) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐶) ↔ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐷)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 | ||
Theorem | en3i 8788* | Equinumerosity inference from an implicit one-to-one onto function. (Contributed by NM, 19-Jul-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝐷 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝑥 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑦 = 𝐶)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 | ||
Theorem | dom2lem 8789* | A mapping (first hypothesis) that is one-to-one (second hypothesis) implies its domain is dominated by its codomain. (Contributed by NM, 24-Jul-2004.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐶 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶):𝐴–1-1→𝐵) | ||
Theorem | dom2d 8790* | A mapping (first hypothesis) that is one-to-one (second hypothesis) implies its domain is dominated by its codomain. (Contributed by NM, 24-Jul-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 20-May-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐶 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐵 ∈ 𝑅 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | dom3d 8791* | A mapping (first hypothesis) that is one-to-one (second hypothesis) implies its domain is dominated by its codomain. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-May-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐶 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | dom2 8792* | A mapping (first hypothesis) that is one-to-one (second hypothesis) implies its domain is dominated by its codomain. 𝐶 and 𝐷 can be read 𝐶(𝑥) and 𝐷(𝑦), as can be inferred from their distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐶 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | dom3 8793* | A mapping (first hypothesis) that is one-to-one (second hypothesis) implies its domain is dominated by its codomain. 𝐶 and 𝐷 can be read 𝐶(𝑥) and 𝐷(𝑦), as can be inferred from their distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-May-2013.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐶 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | idssen 8794 | Equality implies equinumerosity. (Contributed by NM, 30-Apr-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ I ⊆ ≈ | ||
Theorem | ssdomg 8795 | A set dominates its subsets. Theorem 16 of [Suppes] p. 94. (Contributed by NM, 19-Jun-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | ener 8796 | Equinumerosity is an equivalence relation. (Contributed by NM, 19-Mar-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by AV, 1-May-2021.) |
⊢ ≈ Er V | ||
Theorem | ensymb 8797 | Symmetry of equinumerosity. Theorem 2 of [Suppes] p. 92. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ↔ 𝐵 ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ensym 8798 | Symmetry of equinumerosity. Theorem 2 of [Suppes] p. 92. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 → 𝐵 ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ensymi 8799 | Symmetry of equinumerosity. Theorem 2 of [Suppes] p. 92. (Contributed by NM, 25-Sep-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ 𝐵 ≈ 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | ensymd 8800 | Symmetry of equinumerosity. Deduction form of ensym 8798. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ≈ 𝐴) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |