Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 35 of 464) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29181) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29182-30704) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30705-46395) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | rabbia2 3401 | Equivalent wff's yield equal restricted class abstractions. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 26-Jun-2021.) |
⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜓} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜒} | ||
Theorem | rabbidva 3402* | Equivalent wff's yield equal restricted class abstractions (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 28-Nov-2003.) (Proof shortened by SN, 3-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜓} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜒}) | ||
Theorem | rabbidvaOLD 3403* | Obsolete proof of rabbidva 3402 as of 4-Dec-2023. (Contributed by NM, 28-Nov-2003.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜓} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜒}) | ||
Theorem | rabbidv 3404* | Equivalent wff's yield equal restricted class abstractions (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 10-Feb-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜓} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜒}) | ||
Theorem | rabeqf 3405 | Equality theorem for restricted class abstractions, with bound-variable hypotheses instead of distinct variable restrictions. (Contributed by NM, 7-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜑}) | ||
Theorem | rabeqi 3406 | Equality theorem for restricted class abstractions. Inference form of rabeqf 3405. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 26-Jun-2021.) Avoid ax-10 2139, ax-11 2156, ax-12 2173. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 3-Jun-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜑} | ||
Theorem | rabeqiOLD 3407 | Obsolete version of rabeqi 3406 as of 3-Jun-2024. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 26-Jun-2021.) Avoid ax-10 2139 and ax-11 2156. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 20-Aug-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜑} | ||
Theorem | rabeq 3408* | Equality theorem for restricted class abstractions. (Contributed by NM, 15-Oct-2003.) Avoid ax-10 2139, ax-11 2156, ax-12 2173. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 20-Aug-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜑}) | ||
Theorem | rabeqdv 3409* | Equality of restricted class abstractions. Deduction form of rabeq 3408. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 5-Apr-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜓} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜓}) | ||
Theorem | rabeqbidv 3410* | Equality of restricted class abstractions. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 1-Dec-2009.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜓} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜒}) | ||
Theorem | rabeqbidva 3411* | Equality of restricted class abstractions. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜓} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜒}) | ||
Theorem | rabeq2i 3412 | Inference from equality of a class variable and a restricted class abstraction. (Contributed by NM, 16-Feb-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜑} ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↔ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | rabswap 3413 | Swap with a membership relation in a restricted class abstraction. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-2005.) |
⊢ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴} | ||
Theorem | cbvrabw 3414* | Rule to change the bound variable in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. Version of cbvrab 3415 with a disjoint variable condition, which does not require ax-13 2372. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 11-Jul-2011.) (Revised by Gino Giotto, 10-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | cbvrab 3415 | Rule to change the bound variable in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. This version has bound-variable hypotheses in place of distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2372. Use the weaker cbvrabw 3414 when possible. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 11-Jul-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | cbvrabv 3416* | Rule to change the bound variable in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1999.) Require 𝑥, 𝑦 be disjoint to avoid ax-11 2156 and ax-13 2372. (Revised by Steven Nguyen, 4-Dec-2022.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | rabrabi 3417* | Abstract builder restricted to another restricted abstract builder with implicit substitution. (Contributed by AV, 2-Aug-2022.) Avoid ax-10 2139, ax-11 2156 and ax-12 2173. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 12-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑)) ⇒ ⊢ {𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑} ∣ 𝜓} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜓)} | ||
Theorem | rabrabiOLD 3418* | Obsolete version of rabrabi 3417 as of 12-Oct-2024. (Contributed by AV, 2-Aug-2022.) Avoid ax-10 2139 and ax-11 2156. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 20-Aug-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑)) ⇒ ⊢ {𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑} ∣ 𝜓} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜓)} | ||
Theorem | rabeqcda 3419* | When 𝜓 is always true in a context, a restricted class abstraction is equal to the restricting class. Deduction form of rabeqc 3615. (Contributed by Steven Nguyen, 7-Jun-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜓} = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ralrimia 3420 | Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90 (restricted quantifier version). (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 23-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | ralimda 3421 | Deduction quantifying both antecedent and consequent. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 23-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜓 → ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜒)) | ||
Syntax | cvv 3422 | Extend class notation to include the universal class symbol. |
class V | ||
Theorem | vjust 3423 | Justification theorem for df-v 3424. (Contributed by Rodolfo Medina, 27-Apr-2010.) |
⊢ {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 = 𝑥} = {𝑦 ∣ 𝑦 = 𝑦} | ||
Definition | df-v 3424 |
Define the universal class. Definition 5.20 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 21.
Also Definition 2.9 of [Quine] p. 19. The
class V can be described
as the "class of all sets"; vprc 5234
proves that V is not itself a set
in ZF. We will frequently use the expression 𝐴 ∈ V as a short way
to
say "𝐴 is a set", and isset 3435 proves that this expression has the
same meaning as ∃𝑥𝑥 = 𝐴.
In well-founded set theories without urelements, like ZF, the class V is equal to the von Neumann universe. However, the letter "V" does not stand for "von Neumann". The letter "V" was used earlier by Peano in 1889 for the universe of sets, where the letter V is derived from the Latin word "Verum", referring to the true truth constant 𝑇. Peano's notation V was adopted by Whitehead and Russell in Principia Mathematica for the class of all sets in 1910. The class constant V is the first class constant introduced in this database. As a constant, as opposed to a variable, it cannot be substituted with anything, and in particular it is not part of any disjoint variable condition. For a general discussion of the theory of classes, see mmset.html#class 3435. See dfv2 3425 for an alternate definition. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) |
⊢ V = {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 = 𝑥} | ||
Theorem | dfv2 3425 | Alternate definition of the universal class (see df-v 3424). (Contributed by BJ, 30-Nov-2019.) |
⊢ V = {𝑥 ∣ ⊤} | ||
Theorem | vex 3426 | All setvar variables are sets (see isset 3435). Theorem 6.8 of [Quine] p. 43. A shorter proof is possible from eleq2i 2830 but it uses more axioms. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) Remove use of ax-12 2173. (Revised by SN, 28-Aug-2023.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 4-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑥 ∈ V | ||
Theorem | vexOLD 3427 | Obsolete version of vex 3426 as of 4-Sep-2024. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) Remove use of ax-12 2173. (Revised by SN, 28-Aug-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑥 ∈ V | ||
Theorem | elv 3428 | If a proposition is implied by 𝑥 ∈ V (which is true, see vex 3426), then it is true. (Contributed by Peter Mazsa, 13-Oct-2018.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ V → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | elvd 3429 | If a proposition is implied by 𝑥 ∈ V (which is true, see vex 3426) and another antecedent, then it is implied by that other antecedent. Deduction associated with elv 3428. (Contributed by Peter Mazsa, 23-Oct-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ V) → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | el2v 3430 | If a proposition is implied by 𝑥 ∈ V and 𝑦 ∈ V (which is true, see vex 3426), then it is true. (Contributed by Peter Mazsa, 13-Oct-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ V ∧ 𝑦 ∈ V) → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | eqv 3431* | The universe contains every set. (Contributed by NM, 11-Sep-2006.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2139, ax-11 2156, ax-13 2372. (Revised by BJ, 10-Aug-2022.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = V ↔ ∀𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | eqvf 3432 | The universe contains every set. (Contributed by BJ, 15-Jul-2021.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 = V ↔ ∀𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | abv 3433 | The class of sets verifying a property is the universal class if and only if that property is a tautology. The reverse implication (bj-abv 35018) requires fewer axioms. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Mar-2021.) Avoid df-clel 2817, ax-8 2110. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 30-Aug-2024.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 30-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ ({𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} = V ↔ ∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | abvALT 3434 | Alternate proof of abv 3433, shorter but using more axioms. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Mar-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ({𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} = V ↔ ∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | isset 3435* |
Two ways to express that "𝐴 is a set": A class 𝐴 is a
member
of the universal class V (see df-v 3424)
if and only if the class
𝐴 exists (i.e., there exists some set
𝑥
equal to class 𝐴).
Theorem 6.9 of [Quine] p. 43.
A class 𝐴 which is not a set is called a proper class. Conventions: We will often use the expression "𝐴 ∈ V " to mean "𝐴 is a set", for example in uniex 7572. To make some theorems more readily applicable, we will also use the more general expression 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 instead of 𝐴 ∈ V to mean "𝐴 is a set", typically in an antecedent, or in a hypothesis for theorems in deduction form (see for instance uniexg 7571 compared with uniex 7572). That this is more general is seen either by substitution (when the variable 𝑉 has no other occurrences), or by elex 3440. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ V ↔ ∃𝑥 𝑥 = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | issetf 3436 | A version of isset 3435 that does not require 𝑥 and 𝐴 to be distinct. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 6-Jun-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 10-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ V ↔ ∃𝑥 𝑥 = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | isseti 3437* | A way to say "𝐴 is a set" (inference form). (Contributed by NM, 24-Jun-1993.) Remove dependencies on axioms. (Revised by BJ, 13-Jul-2019.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑥 𝑥 = 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | issetri 3438* | A way to say "𝐴 is a set" (inference form). (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥 𝑥 = 𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V | ||
Theorem | eqvisset 3439 | A class equal to a variable is a set. Note the absence of disjoint variable condition, contrary to isset 3435 and issetri 3438. (Contributed by BJ, 27-Apr-2019.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝐴 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | elex 3440 | If a class is a member of another class, then it is a set. Theorem 6.12 of [Quine] p. 44. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝐴 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | elexi 3441 | If a class is a member of another class, then it is a set. Inference associated with elex 3440. (Contributed by NM, 11-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V | ||
Theorem | elexd 3442 | If a class is a member of another class, then it is a set. Deduction associated with elex 3440. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 11-Oct-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | elex2 3443* | If a class contains another class, then it contains some set. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 25-Sep-2011.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → ∃𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | elex22 3444* | If two classes each contain another class, then both contain some set. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 24-Oct-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐶) → ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | prcnel 3445 | A proper class doesn't belong to any class. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 17-Aug-2020.) (Proof shortened by AV, 14-Nov-2020.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝐴 ∈ V → ¬ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) | ||
Theorem | ralv 3446 | A universal quantifier restricted to the universe is unrestricted. (Contributed by NM, 26-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ V 𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | rexv 3447 | An existential quantifier restricted to the universe is unrestricted. (Contributed by NM, 26-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥 ∈ V 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | reuv 3448 | A unique existential quantifier restricted to the universe is unrestricted. (Contributed by NM, 1-Nov-2010.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ V 𝜑 ↔ ∃!𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | rmov 3449 | An at-most-one quantifier restricted to the universe is unrestricted. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (∃*𝑥 ∈ V 𝜑 ↔ ∃*𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | rabab 3450 | A class abstraction restricted to the universe is unrestricted. (Contributed by NM, 27-Dec-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ {𝑥 ∈ V ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} | ||
Theorem | rexcom4b 3451* | Specialized existential commutation lemma. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 1-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐵) ↔ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | ceqsalt 3452* | Closed theorem version of ceqsalg 3454. (Contributed by NM, 28-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 10-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ ((Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ∧ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) → (∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | ceqsralt 3453* | Restricted quantifier version of ceqsalt 3452. (Contributed by NM, 28-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 10-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ ((Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ∧ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) → (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | ceqsalg 3454* | A representation of explicit substitution of a class for a variable, inferred from an implicit substitution hypothesis. For an alternate proof, see ceqsalgALT 3455. (Contributed by NM, 29-Oct-2003.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 29-Sep-2019.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | ceqsalgALT 3455* | Alternate proof of ceqsalg 3454, not using ceqsalt 3452. (Contributed by NM, 29-Oct-2003.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.) (Revised by BJ, 29-Sep-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | ceqsal 3456* | A representation of explicit substitution of a class for a variable, inferred from an implicit substitution hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | ceqsalv 3457* | A representation of explicit substitution of a class for a variable, inferred from an implicit substitution hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1993.) Avoid ax-12 2173. (Revised by SN, 8-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | ceqsalvOLD 3458* | Obsolete version of ceqsalv 3457 as of 8-Sep-2024. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | ceqsralv 3459* | Restricted quantifier version of ceqsalv 3457. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-2013.) Avoid ax-9 2118, ax-12 2173, ax-ext 2709. (Revised by SN, 8-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | ceqsralvOLD 3460* | Obsolete version of ceqsalv 3457 as of 8-Sep-2024. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | gencl 3461* | Implicit substitution for class with embedded variable. (Contributed by NM, 17-May-1996.) |
⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝜒 ∧ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) & ⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜃 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 2gencl 3462* | Implicit substitution for class with embedded variable. (Contributed by NM, 17-May-1996.) |
⊢ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑆 ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝑅 𝐴 = 𝐶) & ⊢ (𝐷 ∈ 𝑆 ↔ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑅 𝐵 = 𝐷) & ⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐶 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝐵 = 𝐷 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑅 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑅) → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑆) → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | 3gencl 3463* | Implicit substitution for class with embedded variable. (Contributed by NM, 17-May-1996.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ 𝑆 ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝑅 𝐴 = 𝐷) & ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ 𝑆 ↔ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑅 𝐵 = 𝐹) & ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ 𝑆 ↔ ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑅 𝐶 = 𝐺) & ⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐷 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝐵 = 𝐹 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝐶 = 𝐺 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑅 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑅 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑅) → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐹 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐺 ∈ 𝑆) → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | cgsexg 3464* | Implicit substitution inference for general classes. (Contributed by NM, 26-Aug-2007.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (∃𝑥(𝜒 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | cgsex2g 3465* | Implicit substitution inference for general classes. (Contributed by NM, 26-Jul-1995.) |
⊢ ((𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵) → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (∃𝑥∃𝑦(𝜒 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | cgsex4g 3466* | An implicit substitution inference for 4 general classes. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1995.) Avoid ax-10 2139, ax-11 2156. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 28-Jun-2024.) |
⊢ (((𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵) ∧ (𝑧 = 𝐶 ∧ 𝑤 = 𝐷)) → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑅 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑅 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑆)) → (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧∃𝑤(𝜒 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | cgsex4gOLD 3467* | Obsolete version of cgsex4g 3466 as of 28-Jun-2024. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1995.) Avoid ax-10 2139. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 20-Aug-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵) ∧ (𝑧 = 𝐶 ∧ 𝑤 = 𝐷)) → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑅 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑅 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑆)) → (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧∃𝑤(𝜒 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | ceqsex 3468* | Elimination of an existential quantifier, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 2-Mar-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 10-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | ceqsexv 3469* | Elimination of an existential quantifier, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 2-Mar-1995.) Avoid ax-12 2173. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 12-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | ceqsexvOLD 3470* | Obsolete version of ceqsexv 3469 as of 12-Oct-2024. (Contributed by NM, 2-Mar-1995.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | ceqsexv2d 3471* | Elimination of an existential quantifier, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 10-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | ceqsex2 3472* | Elimination of two existential quantifiers, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 7-Jun-2006.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜒 & ⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦(𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | ceqsex2v 3473* | Elimination of two existential quantifiers, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 7-Jun-2006.) Avoid ax-10 2139 and ax-11 2156. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 20-Aug-2023.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦(𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | ceqsex3v 3474* | Elimination of three existential quantifiers, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 16-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑧 = 𝐶 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧((𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵 ∧ 𝑧 = 𝐶) ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | ceqsex4v 3475* | Elimination of four existential quantifiers, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 23-Sep-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐷 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑧 = 𝐶 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑤 = 𝐷 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧∃𝑤((𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵) ∧ (𝑧 = 𝐶 ∧ 𝑤 = 𝐷) ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | ceqsex6v 3476* | Elimination of six existential quantifiers, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 21-Sep-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐷 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐸 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐹 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑧 = 𝐶 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑤 = 𝐷 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝑣 = 𝐸 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜂)) & ⊢ (𝑢 = 𝐹 → (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵 ∧ 𝑧 = 𝐶) ∧ (𝑤 = 𝐷 ∧ 𝑣 = 𝐸 ∧ 𝑢 = 𝐹) ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜁) | ||
Theorem | ceqsex8v 3477* | Elimination of eight existential quantifiers, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 23-Sep-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐷 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐸 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐹 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐺 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐻 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑧 = 𝐶 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑤 = 𝐷 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝑣 = 𝐸 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜂)) & ⊢ (𝑢 = 𝐹 → (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) & ⊢ (𝑡 = 𝐺 → (𝜁 ↔ 𝜎)) & ⊢ (𝑠 = 𝐻 → (𝜎 ↔ 𝜌)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢∃𝑡∃𝑠(((𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵) ∧ (𝑧 = 𝐶 ∧ 𝑤 = 𝐷)) ∧ ((𝑣 = 𝐸 ∧ 𝑢 = 𝐹) ∧ (𝑡 = 𝐺 ∧ 𝑠 = 𝐻)) ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜌) | ||
Theorem | gencbvex 3478* | Change of bound variable using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 17-May-1996.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝐴 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝐴 = 𝑦 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝜒 ∧ 𝐴 = 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥(𝜒 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ ∃𝑦(𝜃 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | gencbvex2 3479* | Restatement of gencbvex 3478 with weaker hypotheses. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 6-Dec-2006.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝐴 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝐴 = 𝑦 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜃 → ∃𝑥(𝜒 ∧ 𝐴 = 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥(𝜒 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ ∃𝑦(𝜃 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | gencbval 3480* | Change of bound variable using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 17-May-1996.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝐴 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝐴 = 𝑦 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝜒 ∧ 𝐴 = 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜒 → 𝜑) ↔ ∀𝑦(𝜃 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | sbhypf 3481* | Introduce an explicit substitution into an implicit substitution hypothesis. See also csbhypf 3857. (Contributed by Raph Levien, 10-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐴 → ([𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | vtoclgft 3482 | Closed theorem form of vtoclgf 3493. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by JJ, 11-Aug-2021.) Avoid ax-13 2372. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 6-Oct-2023.) |
⊢ (((Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 ∧ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) ∧ (∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ ∀𝑥𝜑) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | vtocldf 3483 | Implicit substitution of a class for a setvar variable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐴) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | vtocld 3484* | Implicit substitution of a class for a setvar variable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) Avoid ax-10 2139, ax-11 2156, ax-12 2173. (Revised by SN, 2-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐴) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | vtocldOLD 3485* | Obsolete version of vtocld 3484 as of 2-Sep-2024. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐴) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | vtocl2d 3486* | Implicit substitution of two classes for two setvar variables. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 25-Aug-2020.) (Revised by BTernaryTau, 19-Oct-2023.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) & ⊢ ((𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | vtoclf 3487* | Implicit substitution of a class for a setvar variable. This is a generalization of chvar 2395. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | vtocl 3488* | Implicit substitution of a class for a setvar variable. See also vtoclALT 3489. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2139. (Revised by BJ, 29-Nov-2020.) (Proof shortened by SN, 20-Apr-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | vtoclALT 3489* | Alternate proof of vtocl 3488. Shorter but requires more axioms. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | vtocl2 3490* | Implicit substitution of classes for setvar variables. (Contributed by NM, 26-Jul-1995.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ ((𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | vtocl3 3491* | Implicit substitution of classes for setvar variables. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jun-1995.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.) Avoid ax-10 2139 and ax-11 2156. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 20-Aug-2023.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 23-Aug-2023.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ ((𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵 ∧ 𝑧 = 𝐶) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | vtoclb 3492* | Implicit substitution of a class for a setvar variable. (Contributed by NM, 23-Dec-1993.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | vtoclgf 3493 | Implicit substitution of a class for a setvar variable, with bound-variable hypotheses in place of disjoint variable restrictions. (Contributed by NM, 21-Sep-2003.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 10-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | vtoclg1f 3494* | Version of vtoclgf 3493 with one nonfreeness hypothesis replaced with a disjoint variable condition, thus avoiding dependency on ax-11 2156 and ax-13 2372. (Contributed by BJ, 1-May-2019.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | vtoclg 3495* | Implicit substitution of a class expression for a setvar variable. (Contributed by NM, 17-Apr-1995.) Avoid ax-12 2173. (Revised by SN, 20-Apr-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | vtoclgOLD 3496* | Obsolete version of vtoclg 3495 as of 20-Apr-2024. (Contributed by NM, 17-Apr-1995.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | vtoclbg 3497* | Implicit substitution of a class for a setvar variable. (Contributed by NM, 29-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | vtocl2gf 3498 | Implicit substitution of a class for a setvar variable. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-1995.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐵 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜒 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | vtocl3gf 3499 | Implicit substitution of a class for a setvar variable. (Contributed by NM, 10-Aug-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 10-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐵 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝐵 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝐶 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜒 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝜃 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑧 = 𝐶 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋) → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | vtocl2g 3500* | Implicit substitution of 2 classes for 2 setvar variables. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-1995.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2139, ax-11 2156, and ax-13 2372. (Revised by Steven Nguyen, 29-Nov-2022.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝜒) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |