![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 103 of 491) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-30946) |
![]() (30947-32469) |
![]() (32470-49035) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | kmlem14 10201* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 5 <=> 4. (Contributed by NM, 4-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑦 ≠ 𝑣) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑣))) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑦) ∧ ((𝑢 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑦) → 𝑢 = 𝑣)))) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤)) ↔ ∃𝑦∀𝑧∃𝑣∀𝑢(𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | kmlem15 10202* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 5 <=> 4. (Contributed by NM, 4-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑦 ≠ 𝑣) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑣))) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑦) ∧ ((𝑢 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑦) → 𝑢 = 𝑣)))) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ ((¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜒) ↔ ∀𝑧∃𝑣∀𝑢(¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | kmlem16 10203* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4 5 <=> 4. (Contributed by NM, 4-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑦 ≠ 𝑣) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑣))) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑦) ∧ ((𝑢 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑦) → 𝑢 = 𝑣)))) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ ((∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤)) ∨ ∃𝑦(¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜒)) ↔ ∃𝑦∀𝑧∃𝑣∀𝑢((𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜑) ∨ (¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | dfackm 10204* | Equivalence of the Axiom of Choice and Maes' AC ackm 10502. The proof consists of lemmas kmlem1 10188 through kmlem16 10203 and this final theorem. AC is not used for the proof. Note: bypassing the first step (i.e., replacing dfac5 10166 with biid 261) establishes the AC equivalence shown by Maes' writeup. The left-hand-side AC shown here was chosen because it is shorter to display. (Contributed by NM, 13-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧∃𝑣∀𝑢((𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ ¬ 𝑦 = 𝑣) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑣))) ∨ (¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑦) ∧ ((𝑢 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑦) → 𝑢 = 𝑣)))))) | ||
For cardinal arithmetic, we follow [Mendelson] p. 258. Rather than defining operations restricted to cardinal numbers, we use disjoint union df-dju 9938 (⊔) for cardinal addition, Cartesian product df-xp 5694 (×) for cardinal multiplication, and set exponentiation df-map 8866 (↑m) for cardinal exponentiation. Equinumerosity and dominance serve the roles of equality and ordering. If we wanted to, we could easily convert our theorems to actual cardinal number operations via carden 10588, carddom 10591, and cardsdom 10592. The advantage of Mendelson's approach is that we can directly use many equinumerosity theorems that we already have available. | ||
Theorem | undjudom 10205 | Cardinal addition dominates union. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 15-Aug-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ≼ (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | endjudisj 10206 | Equinumerosity of a disjoint union and a union of two disjoint sets. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2007.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) = ∅) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | djuen 10207 | Disjoint unions of equinumerous sets are equinumerous. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ≈ 𝐷) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐶) ≈ (𝐵 ⊔ 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | djuenun 10208 | Disjoint union is equinumerous to union for disjoint sets. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 19-Aug-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ≈ 𝐷 ∧ (𝐵 ∩ 𝐷) = ∅) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐶) ≈ (𝐵 ∪ 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | dju1en 10209 | Cardinal addition with cardinal one (which is the same as ordinal one). Used in proof of Theorem 6J of [Enderton] p. 143. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ¬ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐴 ⊔ 1o) ≈ suc 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dju1dif 10210 | Adding and subtracting one gives back the original cardinality. Similar to pncan 11511 for cardinalities. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-May-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 20-Aug-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (𝐴 ⊔ 1o)) → ((𝐴 ⊔ 1o) ∖ {𝐵}) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dju1p1e2 10211 | 1+1=2 for cardinal number addition, derived from pm54.43 10038 as promised. Theorem *110.643 of Principia Mathematica, vol. II, p. 86, which adds the remark, "The above proposition is occasionally useful." Whitehead and Russell define cardinal addition on collections of all sets equinumerous to 1 and 2 (which for us are proper classes unless we restrict them as in karden 9932), but after applying definitions, our theorem is equivalent. Because we use a disjoint union for cardinal addition (as explained in the comment at the top of this section), we use ≈ instead of =. See dju1p1e2ALT 10212 for a shorter proof that doesn't use pm54.43 10038. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2007.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (1o ⊔ 1o) ≈ 2o | ||
Theorem | dju1p1e2ALT 10212 | Alternate proof of dju1p1e2 10211. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (1o ⊔ 1o) ≈ 2o | ||
Theorem | dju0en 10213 | Cardinal addition with cardinal zero (the empty set). Part (a1) of proof of Theorem 6J of [Enderton] p. 143. (Contributed by NM, 27-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ⊔ ∅) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | xp2dju 10214 | Two times a cardinal number. Exercise 4.56(g) of [Mendelson] p. 258. (Contributed by NM, 27-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (2o × 𝐴) = (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | djucomen 10215 | Commutative law for cardinal addition. Exercise 4.56(c) of [Mendelson] p. 258. (Contributed by NM, 24-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ (𝐵 ⊔ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | djuassen 10216 | Associative law for cardinal addition. Exercise 4.56(c) of [Mendelson] p. 258. (Contributed by NM, 26-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋) → ((𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ⊔ 𝐶) ≈ (𝐴 ⊔ (𝐵 ⊔ 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | xpdjuen 10217 | Cardinal multiplication distributes over cardinal addition. Theorem 6I(3) of [Enderton] p. 142. (Contributed by NM, 26-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝐴 × (𝐵 ⊔ 𝐶)) ≈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) ⊔ (𝐴 × 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | mapdjuen 10218 | Sum of exponents law for cardinal arithmetic. Theorem 6I(4) of [Enderton] p. 142. (Contributed by NM, 27-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝐴 ↑m (𝐵 ⊔ 𝐶)) ≈ ((𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) × (𝐴 ↑m 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | pwdjuen 10219 | Sum of exponents law for cardinal arithmetic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝒫 (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ (𝒫 𝐴 × 𝒫 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | djudom1 10220 | Ordering law for cardinal addition. Exercise 4.56(f) of [Mendelson] p. 258. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 1-Sep-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐶) ≼ (𝐵 ⊔ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | djudom2 10221 | Ordering law for cardinal addition. Theorem 6L(a) of [Enderton] p. 149. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) → (𝐶 ⊔ 𝐴) ≼ (𝐶 ⊔ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | djudoml 10222 | A set is dominated by its disjoint union with another. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝐴 ≼ (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | djuxpdom 10223 | Cartesian product dominates disjoint union for sets with cardinality greater than 1. Similar to Proposition 10.36 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 93. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((1o ≺ 𝐴 ∧ 1o ≺ 𝐵) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≼ (𝐴 × 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | djufi 10224 | The disjoint union of two finite sets is finite. (Contributed by NM, 22-Oct-2004.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≺ ω ∧ 𝐵 ≺ ω) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≺ ω) | ||
Theorem | cdainflem 10225 | Any partition of omega into two pieces (which may be disjoint) contains an infinite subset. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ≈ ω → (𝐴 ≈ ω ∨ 𝐵 ≈ ω)) | ||
Theorem | djuinf 10226 | A set is infinite iff the cardinal sum with itself is infinite. (Contributed by NM, 22-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (ω ≼ 𝐴 ↔ ω ≼ (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | infdju1 10227 | An infinite set is equinumerous to itself added with one. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (ω ≼ 𝐴 → (𝐴 ⊔ 1o) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | pwdju1 10228 | The sum of a powerset with itself is equipotent to the successor powerset. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝒫 𝐴 ⊔ 𝒫 𝐴) ≈ 𝒫 (𝐴 ⊔ 1o)) | ||
Theorem | pwdjuidm 10229 | If the natural numbers inject into 𝐴, then 𝒫 𝐴 is idempotent under cardinal sum. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (ω ≼ 𝐴 → (𝒫 𝐴 ⊔ 𝒫 𝐴) ≈ 𝒫 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | djulepw 10230 | If 𝐴 is idempotent under cardinal sum and 𝐵 is dominated by the power set of 𝐴, then so is the cardinal sum of 𝐴 and 𝐵. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ⊔ 𝐴) ≈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝒫 𝐴) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≼ 𝒫 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | onadju 10231 | The cardinal and ordinal sums are always equinumerous. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 7-Sep-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 +o 𝐵) ≈ (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | cardadju 10232 | The cardinal sum is equinumerous to an ordinal sum of the cardinals. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ ((card‘𝐴) +o (card‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | djunum 10233 | The disjoint union of two numerable sets is numerable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | unnum 10234 | The union of two numerable sets is numerable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | nnadju 10235 | The cardinal and ordinal sums of finite ordinals are equal. For a shorter proof using ax-rep 5284, see nnadjuALT 10236. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 11-Apr-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Feb-2013.) Avoid ax-rep 5284. (Revised by BTernaryTau, 2-Jul-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (card‘(𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵)) = (𝐴 +o 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | nnadjuALT 10236 | Shorter proof of nnadju 10235 using ax-rep 5284. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 11-Apr-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Feb-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (card‘(𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵)) = (𝐴 +o 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | ficardadju 10237 | The disjoint union of finite sets is equinumerous to the ordinal sum of the cardinalities of those sets. (Contributed by BTernaryTau, 3-Jul-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐵 ∈ Fin) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ ((card‘𝐴) +o (card‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | ficardun 10238 | The cardinality of the union of disjoint, finite sets is the ordinal sum of their cardinalities. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 5-Jun-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) Avoid ax-rep 5284. (Revised by BTernaryTau, 3-Jul-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐵 ∈ Fin ∧ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) = ∅) → (card‘(𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) = ((card‘𝐴) +o (card‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | ficardun2 10239 | The cardinality of the union of finite sets is at most the ordinal sum of their cardinalities. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Feb-2013.) Avoid ax-rep 5284. (Revised by BTernaryTau, 3-Jul-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐵 ∈ Fin) → (card‘(𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) ⊆ ((card‘𝐴) +o (card‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | pwsdompw 10240* | Lemma for domtriom 10480. This is the equinumerosity version of the algebraic identity Σ𝑘 ∈ 𝑛(2↑𝑘) = (2↑𝑛) − 1. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑛 ∈ ω ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ suc 𝑛(𝐵‘𝑘) ≈ 𝒫 𝑘) → ∪ 𝑘 ∈ 𝑛 (𝐵‘𝑘) ≺ (𝐵‘𝑛)) | ||
Theorem | unctb 10241 | The union of two countable sets is countable. (Contributed by FL, 25-Aug-2006.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ ω ∧ 𝐵 ≼ ω) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ≼ ω) | ||
Theorem | infdjuabs 10242 | Absorption law for addition to an infinite cardinal. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infunabs 10243 | An infinite set is equinumerous to its union with a smaller one. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infdju 10244 | The sum of two cardinal numbers is their maximum, if one of them is infinite. Proposition 10.41 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 95. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | infdif 10245 | The cardinality of an infinite set does not change after subtracting a strictly smaller one. Example in [Enderton] p. 164. (Contributed by NM, 22-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≺ 𝐴) → (𝐴 ∖ 𝐵) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infdif2 10246 | Cardinality ordering for an infinite class difference. (Contributed by NM, 24-Mar-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴) → ((𝐴 ∖ 𝐵) ≼ 𝐵 ↔ 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | infxpdom 10247 | Dominance law for multiplication with an infinite cardinal. (Contributed by NM, 26-Mar-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴) → (𝐴 × 𝐵) ≼ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infxpabs 10248 | Absorption law for multiplication with an infinite cardinal. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴) ∧ (𝐵 ≠ ∅ ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴)) → (𝐴 × 𝐵) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infunsdom1 10249 | The union of two sets that are strictly dominated by the infinite set 𝑋 is also dominated by 𝑋. This version of infunsdom 10250 assumes additionally that 𝐴 is the smaller of the two. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Dec-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-May-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝑋 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝑋) ∧ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ≺ 𝑋)) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ≺ 𝑋) | ||
Theorem | infunsdom 10250 | The union of two sets that are strictly dominated by the infinite set 𝑋 is also strictly dominated by 𝑋. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-May-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝑋 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝑋) ∧ (𝐴 ≺ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ≺ 𝑋)) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ≺ 𝑋) | ||
Theorem | infxp 10251 | Absorption law for multiplication with an infinite cardinal. Equivalent to Proposition 10.41 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 95. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴) ∧ (𝐵 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅)) → (𝐴 × 𝐵) ≈ (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | pwdjudom 10252 | A property of dominance over a powerset, and a main lemma for gchac 10718. Similar to Lemma 2.3 of [KanamoriPincus] p. 420. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝒫 (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐴) ≼ (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) → 𝒫 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | infpss 10253* | Every infinite set has an equinumerous proper subset, proved without AC or Infinity. Exercise 7 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 91. See also infpssALT 10350. (Contributed by NM, 23-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (ω ≼ 𝐴 → ∃𝑥(𝑥 ⊊ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑥 ≈ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | infmap2 10254* | An exponentiation law for infinite cardinals. Similar to Lemma 6.2 of [Jech] p. 43. Although this version of infmap 10613 avoids the axiom of choice, it requires the powerset of an infinite set to be well-orderable and so is usually not applicable. (Contributed by NM, 1-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((ω ≼ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴 ∧ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ∈ dom card) → (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ≈ {𝑥 ∣ (𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑥 ≈ 𝐵)}) | ||
Theorem | ackbij2lem1 10255 | Lemma for ackbij2 10279. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → 𝒫 𝐴 ⊆ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem1 10256 | Lemma for ackbij2 10279. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (𝐵 ∩ suc 𝐴) = (𝐵 ∩ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem2 10257 | Lemma for ackbij2 10279. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (𝐵 ∩ suc 𝐴) = ({𝐴} ∪ (𝐵 ∩ 𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem3 10258 | Lemma for ackbij2 10279. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → 𝐴 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem4 10259 | Lemma for ackbij2 10279. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → {𝐴} ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem5 10260 | Lemma for ackbij2 10279. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by AV, 18-Jul-2022.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (card‘𝒫 suc 𝐴) = ((card‘𝒫 𝐴) +o (card‘𝒫 𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem6 10261 | Lemma for ackbij2 10279. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin)) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem7 10262* | Lemma for ackbij1 10274. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) → (𝐹‘𝐴) = (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem8 10263* | Lemma for ackbij1 10274. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (𝐹‘{𝐴}) = (card‘𝒫 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem9 10264* | Lemma for ackbij1 10274. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ∧ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) = ∅) → (𝐹‘(𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) = ((𝐹‘𝐴) +o (𝐹‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem10 10265* | Lemma for ackbij1 10274. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹:(𝒫 ω ∩ Fin)⟶ω | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem11 10266* | Lemma for ackbij1 10274. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem12 10267* | Lemma for ackbij1 10274. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵) → (𝐹‘𝐴) ⊆ (𝐹‘𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem13 10268* | Lemma for ackbij1 10274. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹‘∅) = ∅ | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem14 10269* | Lemma for ackbij1 10274. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (𝐹‘{𝐴}) = suc (𝐹‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem15 10270* | Lemma for ackbij1 10274. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin)) ∧ (𝑐 ∈ ω ∧ 𝑐 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ ¬ 𝑐 ∈ 𝐵)) → ¬ (𝐹‘(𝐴 ∩ suc 𝑐)) = (𝐹‘(𝐵 ∩ suc 𝑐))) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem16 10271* | Lemma for ackbij1 10274. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin)) → ((𝐹‘𝐴) = (𝐹‘𝐵) → 𝐴 = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem17 10272* | Lemma for ackbij1 10274. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹:(𝒫 ω ∩ Fin)–1-1→ω | ||
Theorem | ackbij1lem18 10273* | Lemma for ackbij1 10274. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) → ∃𝑏 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin)(𝐹‘𝑏) = suc (𝐹‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij1 10274* | The Ackermann bijection, part 1: each natural number can be uniquely coded in binary as a finite set of natural numbers and conversely. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹:(𝒫 ω ∩ Fin)–1-1-onto→ω | ||
Theorem | ackbij1b 10275* | The Ackermann bijection, part 1b: the bijection from ackbij1 10274 restricts naturally to the powers of particular naturals. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (𝐹 “ 𝒫 𝐴) = (card‘𝒫 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij2lem2 10276* | Lemma for ackbij2 10279. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 dom 𝑥 ↦ (𝐹‘(𝑥 “ 𝑦)))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (rec(𝐺, ∅)‘𝐴):(𝑅1‘𝐴)–1-1-onto→(card‘(𝑅1‘𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | ackbij2lem3 10277* | Lemma for ackbij2 10279. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 dom 𝑥 ↦ (𝐹‘(𝑥 “ 𝑦)))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (rec(𝐺, ∅)‘𝐴) ⊆ (rec(𝐺, ∅)‘suc 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij2lem4 10278* | Lemma for ackbij2 10279. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 dom 𝑥 ↦ (𝐹‘(𝑥 “ 𝑦)))) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) → (rec(𝐺, ∅)‘𝐵) ⊆ (rec(𝐺, ∅)‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ackbij2 10279* | The Ackermann bijection, part 2: hereditarily finite sets can be represented by recursive binary notation. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 ω ∩ Fin) ↦ (card‘∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ({𝑦} × 𝒫 𝑦))) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 dom 𝑥 ↦ (𝐹‘(𝑥 “ 𝑦)))) & ⊢ 𝐻 = ∪ (rec(𝐺, ∅) “ ω) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐻:∪ (𝑅1 “ ω)–1-1-onto→ω | ||
Theorem | r1om 10280 | The set of hereditarily finite sets is countable. See ackbij2 10279 for an explicit bijection that works without Infinity. See also r1omALT 10813. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑅1‘ω) ≈ ω | ||
Theorem | fictb 10281 | A set is countable iff its collection of finite intersections is countable. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 24-Aug-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (𝐴 ≼ ω ↔ (fi‘𝐴) ≼ ω)) | ||
Theorem | cflem 10282* | A lemma used to simplify cofinality computations, showing the existence of the cardinal of an unbounded subset of a set 𝐴. (Contributed by NM, 24-Apr-2004.) Avoid ax-11 2154. (Revised by BTernaryTau, 25-Jul-2025.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ∃𝑥∃𝑦(𝑥 = (card‘𝑦) ∧ (𝑦 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑦 𝑧 ⊆ 𝑤))) | ||
Theorem | cflemOLD 10283* | Obsolete version of cflem 10282 as of 25-Jul-2025. (Contributed by NM, 24-Apr-2004.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ∃𝑥∃𝑦(𝑥 = (card‘𝑦) ∧ (𝑦 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑦 𝑧 ⊆ 𝑤))) | ||
Theorem | cfval 10284* | Value of the cofinality function. Definition B of Saharon Shelah, Cardinal Arithmetic (1994), p. xxx (Roman numeral 30). The cofinality of an ordinal number 𝐴 is the cardinality (size) of the smallest unbounded subset 𝑦 of the ordinal number. Unbounded means that for every member of 𝐴, there is a member of 𝑦 that is at least as large. Cofinality is a measure of how "reachable from below" an ordinal is. (Contributed by NM, 1-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (cf‘𝐴) = ∩ {𝑥 ∣ ∃𝑦(𝑥 = (card‘𝑦) ∧ (𝑦 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑦 𝑧 ⊆ 𝑤))}) | ||
Theorem | cff 10285 | Cofinality is a function on the class of ordinal numbers to the class of cardinal numbers. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ cf:On⟶On | ||
Theorem | cfub 10286* | An upper bound on cofinality. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ (cf‘𝐴) ⊆ ∩ {𝑥 ∣ ∃𝑦(𝑥 = (card‘𝑦) ∧ (𝑦 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ ∪ 𝑦))} | ||
Theorem | cflm 10287* | Value of the cofinality function at a limit ordinal. Part of Definition of cofinality of [Enderton] p. 257. (Contributed by NM, 26-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ Lim 𝐴) → (cf‘𝐴) = ∩ {𝑥 ∣ ∃𝑦(𝑥 = (card‘𝑦) ∧ (𝑦 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 = ∪ 𝑦))}) | ||
Theorem | cf0 10288 | Value of the cofinality function at 0. Exercise 2 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 102. (Contributed by NM, 16-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (cf‘∅) = ∅ | ||
Theorem | cardcf 10289 | Cofinality is a cardinal number. Proposition 11.11 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 103. (Contributed by NM, 24-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ (card‘(cf‘𝐴)) = (cf‘𝐴) | ||
Theorem | cflecard 10290 | Cofinality is bounded by the cardinality of its argument. (Contributed by NM, 24-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ (cf‘𝐴) ⊆ (card‘𝐴) | ||
Theorem | cfle 10291 | Cofinality is bounded by its argument. Exercise 1 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 102. (Contributed by NM, 26-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ (cf‘𝐴) ⊆ 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | cfon 10292 | The cofinality of any set is an ordinal (although it only makes sense when 𝐴 is an ordinal). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ (cf‘𝐴) ∈ On | ||
Theorem | cfeq0 10293 | Only the ordinal zero has cofinality zero. (Contributed by NM, 24-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → ((cf‘𝐴) = ∅ ↔ 𝐴 = ∅)) | ||
Theorem | cfsuc 10294 | Value of the cofinality function at a successor ordinal. Exercise 3 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 102. (Contributed by NM, 23-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (cf‘suc 𝐴) = 1o) | ||
Theorem | cff1 10295* | There is always a map from (cf‘𝐴) to 𝐴 (this is a stronger condition than the definition, which only presupposes a map from some 𝑦 ≈ (cf‘𝐴). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → ∃𝑓(𝑓:(cf‘𝐴)–1-1→𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑤 ∈ (cf‘𝐴)𝑧 ⊆ (𝑓‘𝑤))) | ||
Theorem | cfflb 10296* | If there is a cofinal map from 𝐵 to 𝐴, then 𝐵 is at least (cf‘𝐴). This theorem and cff1 10295 motivate the picture of (cf‘𝐴) as the greatest lower bound of the domain of cofinal maps into 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (∃𝑓(𝑓:𝐵⟶𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝐵 𝑧 ⊆ (𝑓‘𝑤)) → (cf‘𝐴) ⊆ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | cfval2 10297* | Another expression for the cofinality function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (cf‘𝐴) = ∩ 𝑥 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ∣ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 𝑧 ⊆ 𝑤} (card‘𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | coflim 10298* | A simpler expression for the cofinality predicate, at a limit ordinal. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ((Lim 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) → (∪ 𝐵 = 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝑥 ⊆ 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | cflim3 10299* | Another expression for the cofinality function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (Lim 𝐴 → (cf‘𝐴) = ∩ 𝑥 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ∣ ∪ 𝑥 = 𝐴} (card‘𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | cflim2 10300 | The cofinality function is a limit ordinal iff its argument is. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (Lim 𝐴 ↔ Lim (cf‘𝐴)) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |