![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 359 of 473) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-29860) |
![]() (29861-31383) |
![]() (31384-47242) |
Type | Label | Description | ||||||||||||||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Statement | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | csboprabg 35801* | Move class substitution in and out of class abstractions of nested ordered pairs. (Contributed by ML, 25-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌{〈〈𝑦, 𝑧〉, 𝑑〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈〈𝑦, 𝑧〉, 𝑑〉 ∣ [𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑}) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | csbmpo123 35802* | Move class substitution in and out of maps-to notation for operations. (Contributed by ML, 25-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌(𝑦 ∈ 𝑌, 𝑧 ∈ 𝑍 ↦ 𝐷) = (𝑦 ∈ ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝑌, 𝑧 ∈ ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝑍 ↦ ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝐷)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | con1bii2 35803 | A contraposition inference. (Contributed by ML, 18-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | con2bii2 35804 | A contraposition inference. (Contributed by ML, 18-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | vtoclefex 35805* | Implicit substitution of a class for a setvar variable. (Contributed by ML, 17-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝜑) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | rnmptsn 35806* | The range of a function mapping to singletons. (Contributed by ML, 15-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ran (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ {𝑥}) = {𝑢 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑢 = {𝑥}} | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | f1omptsnlem 35807* | This is the core of the proof of f1omptsn 35808, but to avoid the distinct variables on the definitions, we split this proof into two. (Contributed by ML, 15-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ {𝑥}) & ⊢ 𝑅 = {𝑢 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑢 = {𝑥}} ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝑅 | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | f1omptsn 35808* | A function mapping to singletons is bijective onto a set of singletons. (Contributed by ML, 16-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ {𝑥}) & ⊢ 𝑅 = {𝑢 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑢 = {𝑥}} ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝑅 | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | mptsnunlem 35809* | This is the core of the proof of mptsnun 35810, but to avoid the distinct variables on the definitions, we split this proof into two. (Contributed by ML, 16-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ {𝑥}) & ⊢ 𝑅 = {𝑢 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑢 = {𝑥}} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 → 𝐵 = ∪ (𝐹 “ 𝐵)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | mptsnun 35810* | A class 𝐵 is equal to the union of the class of all singletons of elements of 𝐵. (Contributed by ML, 16-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ {𝑥}) & ⊢ 𝑅 = {𝑢 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑢 = {𝑥}} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 → 𝐵 = ∪ (𝐹 “ 𝐵)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | dissneqlem 35811* | This is the core of the proof of dissneq 35812, but to avoid the distinct variables on the definitions, we split this proof into two. (Contributed by ML, 16-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐶 = {𝑢 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑢 = {𝑥}} ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐶 ⊆ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (TopOn‘𝐴)) → 𝐵 = 𝒫 𝐴) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | dissneq 35812* | Any topology that contains every single-point set is the discrete topology. (Contributed by ML, 16-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐶 = {𝑢 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑢 = {𝑥}} ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐶 ⊆ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (TopOn‘𝐴)) → 𝐵 = 𝒫 𝐴) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | exlimim 35813* | Closed form of exlimimd 35814. (Contributed by ML, 17-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((∃𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓)) → 𝜓) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | exlimimd 35814* | Existential elimination rule of natural deduction. (Contributed by ML, 17-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | exellim 35815* | Closed form of exellimddv 35816. See also exlimim 35813 for a more general theorem. (Contributed by ML, 17-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((∃𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝜑)) → 𝜑) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | exellimddv 35816* | Eliminate an antecedent when the antecedent is elementhood, deduction version. See exellim 35815 for the closed form, which requires the use of a universal quantifier. (Contributed by ML, 17-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | topdifinfindis 35817* | Part of Exercise 3 of [Munkres] p. 83. The topology of all subsets 𝑥 of 𝐴 such that the complement of 𝑥 in 𝐴 is infinite, or 𝑥 is the empty set, or 𝑥 is all of 𝐴, is the trivial topology when 𝐴 is finite. (Contributed by ML, 14-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝑇 = {𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ∣ (¬ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥) ∈ Fin ∨ (𝑥 = ∅ ∨ 𝑥 = 𝐴))} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Fin → 𝑇 = {∅, 𝐴}) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | topdifinffinlem 35818* | This is the core of the proof of topdifinffin 35819, but to avoid the distinct variables on the definition, we need to split this proof into two. (Contributed by ML, 17-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝑇 = {𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ∣ (¬ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥) ∈ Fin ∨ (𝑥 = ∅ ∨ 𝑥 = 𝐴))} ⇒ ⊢ (𝑇 ∈ (TopOn‘𝐴) → 𝐴 ∈ Fin) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | topdifinffin 35819* | Part of Exercise 3 of [Munkres] p. 83. The topology of all subsets 𝑥 of 𝐴 such that the complement of 𝑥 in 𝐴 is infinite, or 𝑥 is the empty set, or 𝑥 is all of 𝐴, is a topology only if 𝐴 is finite. (Contributed by ML, 17-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝑇 = {𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ∣ (¬ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥) ∈ Fin ∨ (𝑥 = ∅ ∨ 𝑥 = 𝐴))} ⇒ ⊢ (𝑇 ∈ (TopOn‘𝐴) → 𝐴 ∈ Fin) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | topdifinf 35820* | Part of Exercise 3 of [Munkres] p. 83. The topology of all subsets 𝑥 of 𝐴 such that the complement of 𝑥 in 𝐴 is infinite, or 𝑥 is the empty set, or 𝑥 is all of 𝐴, is a topology if and only if 𝐴 is finite, in which case it is the trivial topology. (Contributed by ML, 17-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝑇 = {𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ∣ (¬ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥) ∈ Fin ∨ (𝑥 = ∅ ∨ 𝑥 = 𝐴))} ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑇 ∈ (TopOn‘𝐴) ↔ 𝐴 ∈ Fin) ∧ (𝑇 ∈ (TopOn‘𝐴) → 𝑇 = {∅, 𝐴})) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | topdifinfeq 35821* | Two different ways of defining the collection from Exercise 3 of [Munkres] p. 83. (Contributed by ML, 18-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ {𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ∣ (¬ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥) ∈ Fin ∨ ((𝐴 ∖ 𝑥) = ∅ ∨ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥) = 𝐴))} = {𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ∣ (¬ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥) ∈ Fin ∨ (𝑥 = ∅ ∨ 𝑥 = 𝐴))} | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | icorempo 35822* | Closed-below, open-above intervals of reals. (Contributed by ML, 26-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = ([,) ↾ (ℝ × ℝ)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ, 𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ {𝑧 ∈ ℝ ∣ (𝑥 ≤ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 < 𝑦)}) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | icoreresf 35823 | Closed-below, open-above intervals of reals map to subsets of reals. (Contributed by ML, 25-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ([,) ↾ (ℝ × ℝ)):(ℝ × ℝ)⟶𝒫 ℝ | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | icoreval 35824* | Value of the closed-below, open-above interval function on reals. (Contributed by ML, 26-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) → (𝐴[,)𝐵) = {𝑧 ∈ ℝ ∣ (𝐴 ≤ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 < 𝐵)}) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | icoreelrnab 35825* | Elementhood in the set of closed-below, open-above intervals of reals. (Contributed by ML, 27-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐼 = ([,) “ (ℝ × ℝ)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐼 ↔ ∃𝑎 ∈ ℝ ∃𝑏 ∈ ℝ 𝑋 = {𝑧 ∈ ℝ ∣ (𝑎 ≤ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 < 𝑏)}) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | isbasisrelowllem1 35826* | Lemma for isbasisrelowl 35829. (Contributed by ML, 27-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐼 = ([,) “ (ℝ × ℝ)) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝑎 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝑏 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝑥 = {𝑧 ∈ ℝ ∣ (𝑎 ≤ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 < 𝑏)}) ∧ (𝑐 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝑑 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝑦 = {𝑧 ∈ ℝ ∣ (𝑐 ≤ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 < 𝑑)})) ∧ (𝑎 ≤ 𝑐 ∧ 𝑏 ≤ 𝑑)) → (𝑥 ∩ 𝑦) ∈ 𝐼) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | isbasisrelowllem2 35827* | Lemma for isbasisrelowl 35829. (Contributed by ML, 27-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐼 = ([,) “ (ℝ × ℝ)) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝑎 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝑏 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝑥 = {𝑧 ∈ ℝ ∣ (𝑎 ≤ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 < 𝑏)}) ∧ (𝑐 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝑑 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝑦 = {𝑧 ∈ ℝ ∣ (𝑐 ≤ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 < 𝑑)})) ∧ (𝑎 ≤ 𝑐 ∧ 𝑑 ≤ 𝑏)) → (𝑥 ∩ 𝑦) ∈ 𝐼) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | icoreclin 35828* | The set of closed-below, open-above intervals of reals is closed under finite intersection. (Contributed by ML, 27-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐼 = ([,) “ (ℝ × ℝ)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐼) → (𝑥 ∩ 𝑦) ∈ 𝐼) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | isbasisrelowl 35829 | The set of all closed-below, open-above intervals of reals form a basis. (Contributed by ML, 27-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐼 = ([,) “ (ℝ × ℝ)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐼 ∈ TopBases | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | icoreunrn 35830 | The union of all closed-below, open-above intervals of reals is the set of reals. (Contributed by ML, 27-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐼 = ([,) “ (ℝ × ℝ)) ⇒ ⊢ ℝ = ∪ 𝐼 | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | istoprelowl 35831 | The set of all closed-below, open-above intervals of reals generate a topology on the reals. (Contributed by ML, 27-Jul-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐼 = ([,) “ (ℝ × ℝ)) ⇒ ⊢ (topGen‘𝐼) ∈ (TopOn‘ℝ) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | icoreelrn 35832* | A class abstraction which is an element of the set of closed-below, open-above intervals of reals. (Contributed by ML, 1-Aug-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐼 = ([,) “ (ℝ × ℝ)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) → {𝑧 ∈ ℝ ∣ (𝐴 ≤ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 < 𝐵)} ∈ 𝐼) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | iooelexlt 35833* | An element of an open interval is not its smallest element. (Contributed by ML, 2-Aug-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ (𝐴(,)𝐵) → ∃𝑦 ∈ (𝐴(,)𝐵)𝑦 < 𝑋) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | relowlssretop 35834 | The lower limit topology on the reals is finer than the standard topology. (Contributed by ML, 1-Aug-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐼 = ([,) “ (ℝ × ℝ)) ⇒ ⊢ (topGen‘ran (,)) ⊆ (topGen‘𝐼) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | relowlpssretop 35835 | The lower limit topology on the reals is strictly finer than the standard topology. (Contributed by ML, 2-Aug-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐼 = ([,) “ (ℝ × ℝ)) ⇒ ⊢ (topGen‘ran (,)) ⊊ (topGen‘𝐼) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | sucneqond 35836 | Inequality of an ordinal set with its successor. Does not use the axiom of regularity. (Contributed by ML, 18-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 = suc 𝑌) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑌 ∈ On) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ≠ 𝑌) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | sucneqoni 35837 | Inequality of an ordinal set with its successor. Does not use the axiom of regularity. (Contributed by ML, 18-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝑋 = suc 𝑌 & ⊢ 𝑌 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ 𝑋 ≠ 𝑌 | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | onsucuni3 35838 | If an ordinal number has a predecessor, then it is successor of that predecessor. (Contributed by ML, 17-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅ ∧ ¬ Lim 𝐵) → 𝐵 = suc ∪ 𝐵) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | 1oequni2o 35839 | The ordinal number 1o is the predecessor of the ordinal number 2o. (Contributed by ML, 19-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 1o = ∪ 2o | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | rdgsucuni 35840 | If an ordinal number has a predecessor, the value of the recursive definition generator at that number in terms of its predecessor. (Contributed by ML, 17-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅ ∧ ¬ Lim 𝐵) → (rec(𝐹, 𝐼)‘𝐵) = (𝐹‘(rec(𝐹, 𝐼)‘∪ 𝐵))) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | rdgeqoa 35841 | If a recursive function with an initial value 𝐴 at step 𝑁 is equal to itself with an initial value 𝐵 at step 𝑀, then every finite number of successor steps will also be equal. (Contributed by ML, 21-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ On ∧ 𝑀 ∈ On ∧ 𝑋 ∈ ω) → ((rec(𝐹, 𝐴)‘𝑁) = (rec(𝐹, 𝐵)‘𝑀) → (rec(𝐹, 𝐴)‘(𝑁 +o 𝑋)) = (rec(𝐹, 𝐵)‘(𝑀 +o 𝑋)))) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | elxp8 35842 | Membership in a Cartesian product. This version requires no quantifiers or dummy variables. See also elxp7 7956. (Contributed by ML, 19-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶) ↔ ((1st ‘𝐴) ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (V × 𝐶))) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | cbveud 35843* | Deduction used to change bound variables in an existential uniqueness quantifier, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by ML, 27-Mar-2021.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑦𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃!𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∃!𝑦𝜒)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | cbvreud 35844* | Deduction used to change bound variables in a restricted existential uniqueness quantifier. (Contributed by ML, 27-Mar-2021.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑦𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜓 ↔ ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝜒)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | difunieq 35845 | The difference of unions is a subset of the union of the difference. (Contributed by ML, 29-Mar-2021.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (∪ 𝐴 ∖ ∪ 𝐵) ⊆ ∪ (𝐴 ∖ 𝐵) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | inunissunidif 35846 | Theorem about subsets of the difference of unions. (Contributed by ML, 29-Mar-2021.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((𝐴 ∩ ∪ 𝐶) = ∅ → (𝐴 ⊆ ∪ 𝐵 ↔ 𝐴 ⊆ ∪ (𝐵 ∖ 𝐶))) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | rdgellim 35847 | Elementhood in a recursive definition at a limit ordinal. (Contributed by ML, 30-Mar-2022.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (((𝐵 ∈ On ∧ Lim 𝐵) ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝑋 ∈ (rec(𝐹, 𝐴)‘𝐶) → 𝑋 ∈ (rec(𝐹, 𝐴)‘𝐵))) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | rdglimss 35848 | A recursive definition at a limit ordinal is a superset of itself at any smaller ordinal. (Contributed by ML, 30-Mar-2022.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (((𝐵 ∈ On ∧ Lim 𝐵) ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵) → (rec(𝐹, 𝐴)‘𝐶) ⊆ (rec(𝐹, 𝐴)‘𝐵)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | rdgssun 35849* | In a recursive definition where each step expands on the previous one using a union, every previous step is a subset of every later step. (Contributed by ML, 1-Apr-2022.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑤 ∈ V ↦ (𝑤 ∪ 𝐵)) & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ On ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝑋) → (rec(𝐹, 𝐴)‘𝑌) ⊆ (rec(𝐹, 𝐴)‘𝑋)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | exrecfnlem 35850* | Lemma for exrecfn 35851. (Contributed by ML, 30-Mar-2022.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑧 ∈ V ↦ (𝑧 ∪ ran (𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↦ 𝐵))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ∀𝑦 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → ∃𝑥(𝐴 ⊆ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 𝐵 ∈ 𝑥)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | exrecfn 35851* | Theorem about the existence of infinite recursive sets. 𝑦 should usually be free in 𝐵. (Contributed by ML, 30-Mar-2022.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ∀𝑦 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → ∃𝑥(𝐴 ⊆ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 𝐵 ∈ 𝑥)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | exrecfnpw 35852* | For any base set, a set which contains the powerset of all of its own elements exists. (Contributed by ML, 30-Mar-2022.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ∃𝑥(𝐴 ⊆ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 𝒫 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finorwe 35853 | If the Axiom of Infinity is denied, every total order is a well-order. The notion of a well-order cannot be usefully expressed without the Axiom of Infinity due to the inability to quantify over proper classes. (Contributed by ML, 5-Oct-2023.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (¬ ω ∈ V → ( < Or 𝐴 → < We 𝐴)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Syntax | cfinxp 35854 | Extend the definition of a class to include Cartesian exponentiation. | ||||||||||||||||||||||
class (𝑈↑↑𝑁) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Definition | df-finxp 35855* |
Define Cartesian exponentiation on a class.
Note that this definition is limited to finite exponents, since it is defined using nested ordered pairs. If tuples of infinite length are needed, or if they might be needed in the future, use df-ixp 8836 or df-map 8767 instead. The main advantage of this definition is that it integrates better with functions and relations. For example if 𝑅 is a subset of (𝐴↑↑2o), then df-br 5106 can be used on it, and df-fv 6504 can also be used, and so on. It's also worth keeping in mind that ((𝑈↑↑𝑀) × (𝑈↑↑𝑁)) is generally not equal to (𝑈↑↑(𝑀 +o 𝑁)). This definition is technical. Use finxp1o 35863 and finxpsuc 35869 for a more standard recursive experience. (Contributed by ML, 16-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝑈↑↑𝑁) = {𝑦 ∣ (𝑁 ∈ ω ∧ ∅ = (rec((𝑛 ∈ ω, 𝑥 ∈ V ↦ if((𝑛 = 1o ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈), ∅, if(𝑥 ∈ (V × 𝑈), 〈∪ 𝑛, (1st ‘𝑥)〉, 〈𝑛, 𝑥〉))), 〈𝑁, 𝑦〉)‘𝑁))} | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | dffinxpf 35856* | This theorem is the same as Definition df-finxp 35855, except that the large function is replaced by a class variable for brevity. (Contributed by ML, 24-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑛 ∈ ω, 𝑥 ∈ V ↦ if((𝑛 = 1o ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈), ∅, if(𝑥 ∈ (V × 𝑈), 〈∪ 𝑛, (1st ‘𝑥)〉, 〈𝑛, 𝑥〉))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑈↑↑𝑁) = {𝑦 ∣ (𝑁 ∈ ω ∧ ∅ = (rec(𝐹, 〈𝑁, 𝑦〉)‘𝑁))} | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxpeq1 35857 | Equality theorem for Cartesian exponentiation. (Contributed by ML, 19-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝑈 = 𝑉 → (𝑈↑↑𝑁) = (𝑉↑↑𝑁)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxpeq2 35858 | Equality theorem for Cartesian exponentiation. (Contributed by ML, 19-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝑀 = 𝑁 → (𝑈↑↑𝑀) = (𝑈↑↑𝑁)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | csbfinxpg 35859* | Distribute proper substitution through Cartesian exponentiation. (Contributed by ML, 25-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌(𝑈↑↑𝑁) = (⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝑈↑↑⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝑁)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxpreclem1 35860* | Lemma for ↑↑ recursion theorems. (Contributed by ML, 17-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ 𝑈 → ∅ = ((𝑛 ∈ ω, 𝑥 ∈ V ↦ if((𝑛 = 1o ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈), ∅, if(𝑥 ∈ (V × 𝑈), 〈∪ 𝑛, (1st ‘𝑥)〉, 〈𝑛, 𝑥〉)))‘〈1o, 𝑋〉)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxpreclem2 35861* | Lemma for ↑↑ recursion theorems. (Contributed by ML, 17-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ V ∧ ¬ 𝑋 ∈ 𝑈) → ¬ ∅ = ((𝑛 ∈ ω, 𝑥 ∈ V ↦ if((𝑛 = 1o ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈), ∅, if(𝑥 ∈ (V × 𝑈), 〈∪ 𝑛, (1st ‘𝑥)〉, 〈𝑛, 𝑥〉)))‘〈1o, 𝑋〉)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxp0 35862 | The value of Cartesian exponentiation at zero. (Contributed by ML, 24-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝑈↑↑∅) = ∅ | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxp1o 35863 | The value of Cartesian exponentiation at one. (Contributed by ML, 17-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝑈↑↑1o) = 𝑈 | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxpreclem3 35864* | Lemma for ↑↑ recursion theorems. (Contributed by ML, 20-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑛 ∈ ω, 𝑥 ∈ V ↦ if((𝑛 = 1o ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈), ∅, if(𝑥 ∈ (V × 𝑈), 〈∪ 𝑛, (1st ‘𝑥)〉, 〈𝑛, 𝑥〉))) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝑁 ∈ ω ∧ 2o ⊆ 𝑁) ∧ 𝑋 ∈ (V × 𝑈)) → 〈∪ 𝑁, (1st ‘𝑋)〉 = (𝐹‘〈𝑁, 𝑋〉)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxpreclem4 35865* | Lemma for ↑↑ recursion theorems. (Contributed by ML, 23-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑛 ∈ ω, 𝑥 ∈ V ↦ if((𝑛 = 1o ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈), ∅, if(𝑥 ∈ (V × 𝑈), 〈∪ 𝑛, (1st ‘𝑥)〉, 〈𝑛, 𝑥〉))) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝑁 ∈ ω ∧ 2o ⊆ 𝑁) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (V × 𝑈)) → (rec(𝐹, 〈𝑁, 𝑦〉)‘𝑁) = (rec(𝐹, 〈∪ 𝑁, (1st ‘𝑦)〉)‘∪ 𝑁)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxpreclem5 35866* | Lemma for ↑↑ recursion theorems. (Contributed by ML, 24-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑛 ∈ ω, 𝑥 ∈ V ↦ if((𝑛 = 1o ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈), ∅, if(𝑥 ∈ (V × 𝑈), 〈∪ 𝑛, (1st ‘𝑥)〉, 〈𝑛, 𝑥〉))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑛 ∈ ω ∧ 1o ∈ 𝑛) → (¬ 𝑥 ∈ (V × 𝑈) → (𝐹‘〈𝑛, 𝑥〉) = 〈𝑛, 𝑥〉)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxpreclem6 35867* | Lemma for ↑↑ recursion theorems. (Contributed by ML, 24-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑛 ∈ ω, 𝑥 ∈ V ↦ if((𝑛 = 1o ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈), ∅, if(𝑥 ∈ (V × 𝑈), 〈∪ 𝑛, (1st ‘𝑥)〉, 〈𝑛, 𝑥〉))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ω ∧ 1o ∈ 𝑁) → (𝑈↑↑𝑁) ⊆ (V × 𝑈)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxpsuclem 35868* | Lemma for finxpsuc 35869. (Contributed by ML, 24-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑛 ∈ ω, 𝑥 ∈ V ↦ if((𝑛 = 1o ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈), ∅, if(𝑥 ∈ (V × 𝑈), 〈∪ 𝑛, (1st ‘𝑥)〉, 〈𝑛, 𝑥〉))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ω ∧ 1o ⊆ 𝑁) → (𝑈↑↑suc 𝑁) = ((𝑈↑↑𝑁) × 𝑈)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxpsuc 35869 | The value of Cartesian exponentiation at a successor. (Contributed by ML, 24-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ω ∧ 𝑁 ≠ ∅) → (𝑈↑↑suc 𝑁) = ((𝑈↑↑𝑁) × 𝑈)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxp2o 35870 | The value of Cartesian exponentiation at two. (Contributed by ML, 19-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝑈↑↑2o) = (𝑈 × 𝑈) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxp3o 35871 | The value of Cartesian exponentiation at three. (Contributed by ML, 24-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝑈↑↑3o) = ((𝑈 × 𝑈) × 𝑈) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxpnom 35872 | Cartesian exponentiation when the exponent is not a natural number defaults to the empty set. (Contributed by ML, 24-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (¬ 𝑁 ∈ ω → (𝑈↑↑𝑁) = ∅) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | finxp00 35873 | Cartesian exponentiation of the empty set to any power is the empty set. (Contributed by ML, 24-Oct-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (∅↑↑𝑁) = ∅ | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | iunctb2 35874 | Using the axiom of countable choice ax-cc 10371, the countable union of countable sets is countable. See iunctb 10510 for a somewhat more general theorem. (Contributed by ML, 10-Dec-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ ω 𝐵 ≼ ω → ∪ 𝑥 ∈ ω 𝐵 ≼ ω) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | domalom 35875* | A class which dominates every natural number is not finite. (Contributed by ML, 14-Dec-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (∀𝑛 ∈ ω 𝑛 ≼ 𝐴 → ¬ 𝐴 ∈ Fin) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | isinf2 35876* | The converse of isinf 9204. Any set that is not finite is literally infinite, in the sense that it contains subsets of arbitrarily large finite cardinality. (It cannot be proven that the set has countably infinite subsets unless AC is invoked.) The proof does not require the Axiom of Infinity. (Contributed by ML, 14-Dec-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (∀𝑛 ∈ ω ∃𝑥(𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑥 ≈ 𝑛) → ¬ 𝐴 ∈ Fin) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | ctbssinf 35877* | Using the axiom of choice, any infinite class has a countable subset. (Contributed by ML, 14-Dec-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (¬ 𝐴 ∈ Fin → ∃𝑥(𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑥 ≈ ω)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | ralssiun 35878* | The index set of an indexed union is a subset of the union when each 𝐵 contains its index. (Contributed by ML, 16-Dec-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝐴 ⊆ ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | nlpineqsn 35879* | For every point 𝑝 of a subset 𝐴 of 𝑋 with no limit points, there exists an open set 𝑛 that intersects 𝐴 only at 𝑝. (Contributed by ML, 23-Mar-2021.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝑋 = ∪ 𝐽 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐽 ∈ Top ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑋 ∧ ((limPt‘𝐽)‘𝐴) = ∅) → ∀𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑛 ∈ 𝐽 (𝑝 ∈ 𝑛 ∧ (𝑛 ∩ 𝐴) = {𝑝})) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | nlpfvineqsn 35880* | Given a subset 𝐴 of 𝑋 with no limit points, there exists a function from each point 𝑝 of 𝐴 to an open set intersecting 𝐴 only at 𝑝. This proof uses the axiom of choice. (Contributed by ML, 23-Mar-2021.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝑋 = ∪ 𝐽 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ((𝐽 ∈ Top ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑋 ∧ ((limPt‘𝐽)‘𝐴) = ∅) → ∃𝑓(𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐽 ∧ ∀𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝑓‘𝑝) ∩ 𝐴) = {𝑝}))) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | fvineqsnf1 35881* | A theorem about functions where the image of every point intersects the domain only at that point. If 𝐽 is a topology and 𝐴 is a set with no limit points, then there exists an 𝐹 such that this antecedent is true. See nlpfvineqsn 35880 for a proof of this fact. (Contributed by ML, 23-Mar-2021.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐽 ∧ ∀𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝐹‘𝑝) ∩ 𝐴) = {𝑝}) → 𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐽) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | fvineqsneu 35882* | A theorem about functions where the image of every point intersects the domain only at that point. (Contributed by ML, 27-Mar-2021.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝐹‘𝑝) ∩ 𝐴) = {𝑝}) → ∀𝑞 ∈ 𝐴 ∃!𝑥 ∈ ran 𝐹 𝑞 ∈ 𝑥) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | fvineqsneq 35883* | A theorem about functions where the image of every point intersects the domain only at that point. (Contributed by ML, 28-Mar-2021.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝐹‘𝑝) ∩ 𝐴) = {𝑝}) ∧ (𝑍 ⊆ ran 𝐹 ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ ∪ 𝑍)) → 𝑍 = ran 𝐹) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
This section contains a few proofs of theorems found in the pi-base database. The pi-base site can be found at <https://topology.pi-base.org/>. Definitions of topological properties are theorems labeled pibpN, where N is the property number in pi-base. For example, pibp19 35885 defines countably compact topologies. Proofs of theorems are similarly labeled pibtN, for example pibt2 35888. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | pibp16 35884* | Property P000016 of pi-base. The class of compact topologies. A space 𝑋 is compact if every open cover of 𝑋 has a finite subcover. This theorem is just a relabeled copy of iscmp 22739. (Contributed by ML, 8-Dec-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝑋 = ∪ 𝐽 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐽 ∈ Comp ↔ (𝐽 ∈ Top ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 𝐽(𝑋 = ∪ 𝑦 → ∃𝑧 ∈ (𝒫 𝑦 ∩ Fin)𝑋 = ∪ 𝑧))) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | pibp19 35885* | Property P000019 of pi-base. The class of countably compact topologies. A space 𝑋 is countably compact if every countable open cover of 𝑋 has a finite subcover. (Contributed by ML, 8-Dec-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝑋 = ∪ 𝐽 & ⊢ 𝐶 = {𝑥 ∈ Top ∣ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 𝑥((∪ 𝑥 = ∪ 𝑦 ∧ 𝑦 ≼ ω) → ∃𝑧 ∈ (𝒫 𝑦 ∩ Fin)∪ 𝑥 = ∪ 𝑧)} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐽 ∈ 𝐶 ↔ (𝐽 ∈ Top ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 𝐽((𝑋 = ∪ 𝑦 ∧ 𝑦 ≼ ω) → ∃𝑧 ∈ (𝒫 𝑦 ∩ Fin)𝑋 = ∪ 𝑧))) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | pibp21 35886* | Property P000021 of pi-base. The class of weakly countably compact topologies, or limit point compact topologies. A space 𝑋 is weakly countably compact if every infinite subset of 𝑋 has a limit point. (Contributed by ML, 9-Dec-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝑋 = ∪ 𝐽 & ⊢ 𝑊 = {𝑥 ∈ Top ∣ ∀𝑦 ∈ (𝒫 ∪ 𝑥 ∖ Fin)∃𝑧 ∈ ∪ 𝑥𝑧 ∈ ((limPt‘𝑥)‘𝑦)} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐽 ∈ 𝑊 ↔ (𝐽 ∈ Top ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ (𝒫 𝑋 ∖ Fin)∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑋 𝑧 ∈ ((limPt‘𝐽)‘𝑦))) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | pibt1 35887* | Theorem T000001 of pi-base. A compact topology is also countably compact. See pibp16 35884 and pibp19 35885 for the definitions of the relevant properties. (Contributed by ML, 8-Dec-2020.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝐶 = {𝑥 ∈ Top ∣ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 𝑥((∪ 𝑥 = ∪ 𝑦 ∧ 𝑦 ≼ ω) → ∃𝑧 ∈ (𝒫 𝑦 ∩ Fin)∪ 𝑥 = ∪ 𝑧)} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐽 ∈ Comp → 𝐽 ∈ 𝐶) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | pibt2 35888* | Theorem T000002 of pi-base, a countably compact topology is also weakly countably compact. See pibp19 35885 and pibp21 35886 for the definitions of the relevant properties. This proof uses the axiom of choice. (Contributed by ML, 30-Mar-2021.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝑋 = ∪ 𝐽 & ⊢ 𝐶 = {𝑥 ∈ Top ∣ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 𝑥((∪ 𝑥 = ∪ 𝑦 ∧ 𝑦 ≼ ω) → ∃𝑧 ∈ (𝒫 𝑦 ∩ Fin)∪ 𝑥 = ∪ 𝑧)} & ⊢ 𝑊 = {𝑥 ∈ Top ∣ ∀𝑦 ∈ (𝒫 ∪ 𝑥 ∖ Fin)∃𝑧 ∈ ∪ 𝑥𝑧 ∈ ((limPt‘𝑥)‘𝑦)} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐽 ∈ 𝐶 → 𝐽 ∈ 𝑊) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | wl-section-prop 35889 |
Intuitionistic logic is now developed separately, so we need not first
focus on intuitionally valid axioms ax-1 6 and
ax-2 7
any longer.
Alternatively, I start from Jan Lukasiewicz's axiom system here, i.e., ax-mp 5, ax-luk1 35890, ax-luk2 35891 and ax-luk3 35892. I rather copy this system than use luk-1 1657 to luk-3 1659, since the latter are theorems, while we need axioms here. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 23-Feb-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Axiom | ax-luk1 35890 |
1 of 3 axioms for propositional calculus due to Lukasiewicz. Copy of
luk-1 1657 and imim1 83, but introduced as an axiom. It
focuses on a basic
property of a valid implication, namely that the consequent has to be true
whenever the antecedent is. So if 𝜑 and 𝜓 are somehow
parametrized expressions, then 𝜑 → 𝜓 states that 𝜑 strengthen
𝜓, in that 𝜑 holds only for a (often
proper) subset of those
parameters making 𝜓 true. We easily accept, that when
𝜓 is
stronger than 𝜒 and, at the same time 𝜑 is
stronger than
𝜓, then 𝜑 must be stronger than
𝜒.
This transitivity is
expressed in this axiom.
A particular result of this strengthening property comes into play if the antecedent holds unconditionally. Then the consequent must hold unconditionally as well. This specialization is the foundational idea behind logical conclusion. Such conclusion is best expressed in so-called immediate versions of this axiom like imim1i 63 or syl 17. Note that these forms are weaker replacements (i.e. just frequent specialization) of the closed form presented here, hence a mere convenience. We can identify in this axiom up to three antecedents, followed by a consequent. The number of antecedents is not really fixed; the fewer we are willing to "see", the more complex the consequent grows. On the other side, since 𝜒 is a variable capable of assuming an implication itself, we might find even more antecedents after some substitution of 𝜒. This shows that the ideas of antecedent and consequent in expressions like this depends on, and can adapt to, our current interpretation of the whole expression. In this axiom, up to two antecedents happen to be of complex nature themselves, i.e. are an embedded implication. Logically, this axiom is a compact notion of simpler expressions, which I will later coin implication chains. Herein all antecedents and the consequent appear as simple variables, or their negation. Any propositional expression is equivalent to a set of such chains. This axiom, for example, is dissected into following chains, from which it can be recovered losslessly: (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜒))); (¬ 𝜑 → (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜒))); (𝜓 → (¬ 𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒))); (¬ 𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒))). (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Axiom | ax-luk2 35891 |
2 of 3 axioms for propositional calculus due to Lukasiewicz. Copy of
luk-2 1658 or pm2.18 128, but introduced as an axiom. The core idea
behind
this axiom is, that if something can be implied from both an antecedent,
and separately from its negation, then the antecedent is irrelevant to the
consequent, and can safely be dropped. This is perhaps better seen from
the following slightly extended version (related to pm2.65 192):
((𝜑 → 𝜑) → ((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜑) → 𝜑)). (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ ((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜑) → 𝜑) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Axiom | ax-luk3 35892 |
3 of 3 axioms for propositional calculus due to Lukasiewicz. Copy of
luk-3 1659 and pm2.24 124, but introduced as an axiom.
One might think that the similar pm2.21 123 (¬ 𝜑 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) is
a valid replacement for this axiom. But this is not true, ax-3 8 is not
derivable from this modification.
This can be shown by designing carefully operators ¬ and → on a
finite set of primitive statements. In propositional logic such
statements are ⊤ and ⊥, but we can assume more and other
primitives in our universe of statements. So we denote our primitive
statements as phi0 , phi1 and phi2. The actual meaning of the statements
are not important in this context, it rather counts how they behave under
our operations ¬ and →, and which of them we assume to hold
unconditionally (phi1, phi2). For our disproving model, I give that
information in tabular form below. The interested reader may check by
hand, that all possible interpretations of ax-mp 5, ax-luk1 35890, ax-luk2 35891
and pm2.21 123 result in phi1 or phi2, meaning they always hold. But for
wl-luk-ax3 35904 we can find a counter example resulting in phi0, not a
statement always true.
The verification of a particular set of axioms in a given model is tedious
and error prone, so I wrote a computer program, first checking this for
me, and second, hunting for a counter example. Here is the result, after
9165 fruitlessly computer generated models:
ax-3 fails for phi2, phi2 number of statements: 3 always true phi1 phi2 Negation is defined as ----------------------------------------------------------------------
Implication is defined as ----------------------------------------------------------------------
(Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝜑 → (¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | wl-section-boot 35893 | In this section, I provide the first steps needed for convenient proving. The presented theorems follow no common concept other than being useful in themselves, and apt to rederive ax-1 6, ax-2 7 and ax-3 8. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | wl-luk-imim1i 35894 | Inference adding common consequents in an implication, thereby interchanging the original antecedent and consequent. Copy of imim1i 63 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | wl-luk-syl 35895 | An inference version of the transitive laws for implication luk-1 1657. Copy of syl 17 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | wl-luk-imtrid 35896 | A syllogism rule of inference. The first premise is used to replace the second antecedent of the second premise. Copy of syl5 34 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜃)) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | wl-luk-pm2.18d 35897 | Deduction based on reductio ad absurdum. Copy of pm2.18d 127 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓 → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | wl-luk-con4i 35898 | Inference rule. Copy of con4i 114 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜑) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | wl-luk-pm2.24i 35899 | Inference rule. Copy of pm2.24i 150 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
Theorem | wl-luk-a1i 35900 | Inference rule. Copy of a1i 11 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) | ||||||||||||||||||||||
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜑) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |