![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 377 of 489) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-30950) |
![]() (30951-32473) |
![]() (32474-48899) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | poimirlem21 37601* | Lemma for poimir 37613 stating that, given a face not on a back face of the cube and a simplex in which it's opposite the final point of the walk, there exists exactly one other simplex containing it. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑡 ∈ ((((0..^𝐾) ↑m (1...𝑁)) × {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)}) × (0...𝑁)) ∣ 𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ (0...(𝑁 − 1)) ↦ ⦋if(𝑦 < (2nd ‘𝑡), 𝑦, (𝑦 + 1)) / 𝑗⦌((1st ‘(1st ‘𝑡)) ∘f + ((((2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑡)) “ (1...𝑗)) × {1}) ∪ (((2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑡)) “ ((𝑗 + 1)...𝑁)) × {0}))))} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:(0...(𝑁 − 1))⟶((0...𝐾) ↑m (1...𝑁))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝑆) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁)) → ∃𝑝 ∈ ran 𝐹(𝑝‘𝑛) ≠ 0) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (2nd ‘𝑇) = 𝑁) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃!𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 𝑧 ≠ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | poimirlem22 37602* | Lemma for poimir 37613, that a given face belongs to exactly two simplices, provided it's not on the boundary of the cube. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑡 ∈ ((((0..^𝐾) ↑m (1...𝑁)) × {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)}) × (0...𝑁)) ∣ 𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ (0...(𝑁 − 1)) ↦ ⦋if(𝑦 < (2nd ‘𝑡), 𝑦, (𝑦 + 1)) / 𝑗⦌((1st ‘(1st ‘𝑡)) ∘f + ((((2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑡)) “ (1...𝑗)) × {1}) ∪ (((2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑡)) “ ((𝑗 + 1)...𝑁)) × {0}))))} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:(0...(𝑁 − 1))⟶((0...𝐾) ↑m (1...𝑁))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝑆) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁)) → ∃𝑝 ∈ ran 𝐹(𝑝‘𝑛) ≠ 0) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁)) → ∃𝑝 ∈ ran 𝐹(𝑝‘𝑛) ≠ 𝐾) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃!𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 𝑧 ≠ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | poimirlem23 37603* | Lemma for poimir 37613, two ways of expressing the property that a face is not on the back face of the cube. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇:(1...𝑁)⟶(0..^𝐾)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑉 ∈ (0...𝑁)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑝 ∈ ran (𝑦 ∈ (0...(𝑁 − 1)) ↦ ⦋if(𝑦 < 𝑉, 𝑦, (𝑦 + 1)) / 𝑗⦌(𝑇 ∘f + (((𝑈 “ (1...𝑗)) × {1}) ∪ ((𝑈 “ ((𝑗 + 1)...𝑁)) × {0}))))(𝑝‘𝑁) ≠ 0 ↔ ¬ (𝑉 = 𝑁 ∧ ((𝑇‘𝑁) = 0 ∧ (𝑈‘𝑁) = 𝑁)))) | ||
Theorem | poimirlem24 37604* | Lemma for poimir 37613, two ways of expressing that a simplex has an admissible face on the back face of the cube. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝑝 = ((1st ‘𝑠) ∘f + ((((2nd ‘𝑠) “ (1...𝑗)) × {1}) ∪ (((2nd ‘𝑠) “ ((𝑗 + 1)...𝑁)) × {0}))) → 𝐵 = 𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑝:(1...𝑁)⟶(0...𝐾)) → 𝐵 ∈ (0...𝑁)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇:(1...𝑁)⟶(0..^𝐾)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑉 ∈ (0...𝑁)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥 ∈ (((0...𝐾) ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↑m (0...(𝑁 − 1)))(𝑥 = (𝑦 ∈ (0...(𝑁 − 1)) ↦ ⦋if(𝑦 < 𝑉, 𝑦, (𝑦 + 1)) / 𝑗⦌(𝑇 ∘f + (((𝑈 “ (1...𝑗)) × {1}) ∪ ((𝑈 “ ((𝑗 + 1)...𝑁)) × {0})))) ∧ ((0...(𝑁 − 1)) ⊆ ran (𝑝 ∈ ran 𝑥 ↦ 𝐵) ∧ ∃𝑝 ∈ ran 𝑥(𝑝‘𝑁) ≠ 0)) ↔ (∀𝑖 ∈ (0...(𝑁 − 1))∃𝑗 ∈ ((0...𝑁) ∖ {𝑉})𝑖 = ⦋〈𝑇, 𝑈〉 / 𝑠⦌𝐶 ∧ ¬ (𝑉 = 𝑁 ∧ ((𝑇‘𝑁) = 0 ∧ (𝑈‘𝑁) = 𝑁))))) | ||
Theorem | poimirlem25 37605* | Lemma for poimir 37613 stating that for a given simplex such that no vertex maps to 𝑁, the number of admissible faces is even. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝑝 = ((1st ‘𝑠) ∘f + ((((2nd ‘𝑠) “ (1...𝑗)) × {1}) ∪ (((2nd ‘𝑠) “ ((𝑗 + 1)...𝑁)) × {0}))) → 𝐵 = 𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑝:(1...𝑁)⟶(0...𝐾)) → 𝐵 ∈ (0...𝑁)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇:(1...𝑁)⟶(0..^𝐾)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑗 ∈ (0...𝑁)) → 𝑁 ≠ ⦋〈𝑇, 𝑈〉 / 𝑠⦌𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 2 ∥ (♯‘{𝑦 ∈ (0...𝑁) ∣ ∀𝑖 ∈ (0...(𝑁 − 1))∃𝑗 ∈ ((0...𝑁) ∖ {𝑦})𝑖 = ⦋〈𝑇, 𝑈〉 / 𝑠⦌𝐶})) | ||
Theorem | poimirlem26 37606* | Lemma for poimir 37613 showing an even difference between the number of admissible faces and the number of admissible simplices. Equation (6) of [Kulpa] p. 548. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝑝 = ((1st ‘𝑠) ∘f + ((((2nd ‘𝑠) “ (1...𝑗)) × {1}) ∪ (((2nd ‘𝑠) “ ((𝑗 + 1)...𝑁)) × {0}))) → 𝐵 = 𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑝:(1...𝑁)⟶(0...𝐾)) → 𝐵 ∈ (0...𝑁)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 2 ∥ ((♯‘{𝑡 ∈ ((((0..^𝐾) ↑m (1...𝑁)) × {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)}) × (0...𝑁)) ∣ ∀𝑖 ∈ (0...(𝑁 − 1))∃𝑗 ∈ ((0...𝑁) ∖ {(2nd ‘𝑡)})𝑖 = ⦋(1st ‘𝑡) / 𝑠⦌𝐶}) − (♯‘{𝑠 ∈ (((0..^𝐾) ↑m (1...𝑁)) × {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)}) ∣ ∀𝑖 ∈ (0...𝑁)∃𝑗 ∈ (0...𝑁)𝑖 = 𝐶}))) | ||
Theorem | poimirlem27 37607* | Lemma for poimir 37613 showing that the difference between admissible faces in the whole cube and admissible faces on the back face is even. Equation (7) of [Kulpa] p. 548. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝑝 = ((1st ‘𝑠) ∘f + ((((2nd ‘𝑠) “ (1...𝑗)) × {1}) ∪ (((2nd ‘𝑠) “ ((𝑗 + 1)...𝑁)) × {0}))) → 𝐵 = 𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑝:(1...𝑁)⟶(0...𝐾)) → 𝐵 ∈ (0...𝑁)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∧ 𝑝:(1...𝑁)⟶(0...𝐾) ∧ (𝑝‘𝑛) = 0)) → 𝐵 < 𝑛) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∧ 𝑝:(1...𝑁)⟶(0...𝐾) ∧ (𝑝‘𝑛) = 𝐾)) → 𝐵 ≠ (𝑛 − 1)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 2 ∥ ((♯‘{𝑡 ∈ ((((0..^𝐾) ↑m (1...𝑁)) × {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)}) × (0...𝑁)) ∣ ∀𝑖 ∈ (0...(𝑁 − 1))∃𝑗 ∈ ((0...𝑁) ∖ {(2nd ‘𝑡)})𝑖 = ⦋(1st ‘𝑡) / 𝑠⦌𝐶}) − (♯‘{𝑠 ∈ (((0..^𝐾) ↑m (1...𝑁)) × {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)}) ∣ (∀𝑖 ∈ (0...(𝑁 − 1))∃𝑗 ∈ (0...(𝑁 − 1))𝑖 = 𝐶 ∧ ((1st ‘𝑠)‘𝑁) = 0 ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑠)‘𝑁) = 𝑁)}))) | ||
Theorem | poimirlem28 37608* | Lemma for poimir 37613, a variant of Sperner's lemma. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝑝 = ((1st ‘𝑠) ∘f + ((((2nd ‘𝑠) “ (1...𝑗)) × {1}) ∪ (((2nd ‘𝑠) “ ((𝑗 + 1)...𝑁)) × {0}))) → 𝐵 = 𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑝:(1...𝑁)⟶(0...𝐾)) → 𝐵 ∈ (0...𝑁)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∧ 𝑝:(1...𝑁)⟶(0...𝐾) ∧ (𝑝‘𝑛) = 0)) → 𝐵 < 𝑛) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∧ 𝑝:(1...𝑁)⟶(0...𝐾) ∧ (𝑝‘𝑛) = 𝐾)) → 𝐵 ≠ (𝑛 − 1)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐾 ∈ ℕ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑠 ∈ (((0..^𝐾) ↑m (1...𝑁)) × {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)})∀𝑖 ∈ (0...𝑁)∃𝑗 ∈ (0...𝑁)𝑖 = 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | poimirlem29 37609* | Lemma for poimir 37613 connecting cubes of the tessellation to neighborhoods. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ 𝐼 = ((0[,]1) ↑m (1...𝑁)) & ⊢ 𝑅 = (∏t‘((1...𝑁) × {(topGen‘ran (,))})) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ ((𝑅 ↾t 𝐼) Cn 𝑅)) & ⊢ 𝑋 = ((𝐹‘(((1st ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) ∘f + ((((2nd ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) “ (1...𝑗)) × {1}) ∪ (((2nd ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) “ ((𝑗 + 1)...𝑁)) × {0}))) ∘f / ((1...𝑁) × {𝑘})))‘𝑛) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐺:ℕ⟶((ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) × {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)})) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑘 ∈ ℕ) → ran (1st ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) ⊆ (0..^𝑘)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑘 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∧ 𝑟 ∈ { ≤ , ◡ ≤ })) → ∃𝑗 ∈ (0...𝑁)0𝑟𝑋) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑖 ∈ ℕ ∃𝑘 ∈ (ℤ≥‘𝑖)∀𝑚 ∈ (1...𝑁)(((1st ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) ∘f / ((1...𝑁) × {𝑘}))‘𝑚) ∈ ((𝐶‘𝑚)(ball‘((abs ∘ − ) ↾ (ℝ × ℝ)))(1 / 𝑖)) → ∀𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁)∀𝑣 ∈ (𝑅 ↾t 𝐼)(𝐶 ∈ 𝑣 → ∀𝑟 ∈ { ≤ , ◡ ≤ }∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑣 0𝑟((𝐹‘𝑧)‘𝑛)))) | ||
Theorem | poimirlem30 37610* | Lemma for poimir 37613 combining poimirlem29 37609 with bwth 23439. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ 𝐼 = ((0[,]1) ↑m (1...𝑁)) & ⊢ 𝑅 = (∏t‘((1...𝑁) × {(topGen‘ran (,))})) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ ((𝑅 ↾t 𝐼) Cn 𝑅)) & ⊢ 𝑋 = ((𝐹‘(((1st ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) ∘f + ((((2nd ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) “ (1...𝑗)) × {1}) ∪ (((2nd ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) “ ((𝑗 + 1)...𝑁)) × {0}))) ∘f / ((1...𝑁) × {𝑘})))‘𝑛) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐺:ℕ⟶((ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) × {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)})) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑘 ∈ ℕ) → ran (1st ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) ⊆ (0..^𝑘)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑘 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∧ 𝑟 ∈ { ≤ , ◡ ≤ })) → ∃𝑗 ∈ (0...𝑁)0𝑟𝑋) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐼 ∀𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁)∀𝑣 ∈ (𝑅 ↾t 𝐼)(𝑐 ∈ 𝑣 → ∀𝑟 ∈ { ≤ , ◡ ≤ }∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑣 0𝑟((𝐹‘𝑧)‘𝑛))) | ||
Theorem | poimirlem31 37611* | Lemma for poimir 37613, assigning values to the vertices of the tessellation that meet the hypotheses of both poimirlem30 37610 and poimirlem28 37608. Equation (2) of [Kulpa] p. 547. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ 𝐼 = ((0[,]1) ↑m (1...𝑁)) & ⊢ 𝑅 = (∏t‘((1...𝑁) × {(topGen‘ran (,))})) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ ((𝑅 ↾t 𝐼) Cn 𝑅)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐼 ∧ (𝑧‘𝑛) = 0)) → ((𝐹‘𝑧)‘𝑛) ≤ 0) & ⊢ 𝑃 = ((1st ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) ∘f + ((((2nd ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) “ (1...𝑗)) × {1}) ∪ (((2nd ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) “ ((𝑗 + 1)...𝑁)) × {0}))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐺:ℕ⟶((ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) × {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:(1...𝑁)–1-1-onto→(1...𝑁)})) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑘 ∈ ℕ) → ran (1st ‘(𝐺‘𝑘)) ⊆ (0..^𝑘)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑘 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑖 ∈ (0...𝑁))) → ∃𝑗 ∈ (0...𝑁)𝑖 = sup(({0} ∪ {𝑎 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∣ ∀𝑏 ∈ (1...𝑎)(0 ≤ ((𝐹‘(𝑃 ∘f / ((1...𝑁) × {𝑘})))‘𝑏) ∧ (𝑃‘𝑏) ≠ 0)}), ℝ, < )) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑘 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∧ 𝑟 ∈ { ≤ , ◡ ≤ })) → ∃𝑗 ∈ (0...𝑁)0𝑟((𝐹‘(𝑃 ∘f / ((1...𝑁) × {𝑘})))‘𝑛)) | ||
Theorem | poimirlem32 37612* | Lemma for poimir 37613, combining poimirlem28 37608, poimirlem30 37610, and poimirlem31 37611 to get Equation (1) of [Kulpa] p. 547. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ 𝐼 = ((0[,]1) ↑m (1...𝑁)) & ⊢ 𝑅 = (∏t‘((1...𝑁) × {(topGen‘ran (,))})) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ ((𝑅 ↾t 𝐼) Cn 𝑅)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐼 ∧ (𝑧‘𝑛) = 0)) → ((𝐹‘𝑧)‘𝑛) ≤ 0) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐼 ∧ (𝑧‘𝑛) = 1)) → 0 ≤ ((𝐹‘𝑧)‘𝑛)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐼 ∀𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁)∀𝑣 ∈ (𝑅 ↾t 𝐼)(𝑐 ∈ 𝑣 → ∀𝑟 ∈ { ≤ , ◡ ≤ }∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑣 0𝑟((𝐹‘𝑧)‘𝑛))) | ||
Theorem | poimir 37613* | Poincare-Miranda theorem. Theorem on [Kulpa] p. 547. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ 𝐼 = ((0[,]1) ↑m (1...𝑁)) & ⊢ 𝑅 = (∏t‘((1...𝑁) × {(topGen‘ran (,))})) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ ((𝑅 ↾t 𝐼) Cn 𝑅)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐼 ∧ (𝑧‘𝑛) = 0)) → ((𝐹‘𝑧)‘𝑛) ≤ 0) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐼 ∧ (𝑧‘𝑛) = 1)) → 0 ≤ ((𝐹‘𝑧)‘𝑛)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐼 (𝐹‘𝑐) = ((1...𝑁) × {0})) | ||
Theorem | broucube 37614* | Brouwer - or as Kulpa calls it, "Bohl-Brouwer" - fixed point theorem for the unit cube. Theorem on [Kulpa] p. 548. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ 𝐼 = ((0[,]1) ↑m (1...𝑁)) & ⊢ 𝑅 = (∏t‘((1...𝑁) × {(topGen‘ran (,))})) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ ((𝑅 ↾t 𝐼) Cn (𝑅 ↾t 𝐼))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐼 𝑐 = (𝐹‘𝑐)) | ||
Theorem | heicant 37615 | Heine-Cantor theorem: a continuous mapping between metric spaces whose domain is compact is uniformly continuous. Theorem on [Rosenlicht] p. 80. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 13-Aug-2018.) (Proof shortened by AV, 27-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ (∞Met‘𝑋)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐷 ∈ (∞Met‘𝑌)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (MetOpen‘𝐶) ∈ Comp) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ≠ ∅) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑌 ≠ ∅) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((metUnif‘𝐶) Cnu(metUnif‘𝐷)) = ((MetOpen‘𝐶) Cn (MetOpen‘𝐷))) | ||
Theorem | opnmbllem0 37616* | Lemma for ismblfin 37621; could also be used to shorten proof of opnmbllem 25655. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 13-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (topGen‘ran (,)) → ∪ ([,] “ {𝑧 ∈ ran (𝑥 ∈ ℤ, 𝑦 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ 〈(𝑥 / (2↑𝑦)), ((𝑥 + 1) / (2↑𝑦))〉) ∣ ([,]‘𝑧) ⊆ 𝐴}) = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | mblfinlem1 37617* | Lemma for ismblfin 37621, ordering the sets of dyadic intervals that are antichains under subset and whose unions are contained entirely in 𝐴. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 13-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (topGen‘ran (,)) ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) → ∃𝑓 𝑓:ℕ–1-1-onto→{𝑎 ∈ {𝑏 ∈ ran (𝑥 ∈ ℤ, 𝑦 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ 〈(𝑥 / (2↑𝑦)), ((𝑥 + 1) / (2↑𝑦))〉) ∣ ([,]‘𝑏) ⊆ 𝐴} ∣ ∀𝑐 ∈ {𝑏 ∈ ran (𝑥 ∈ ℤ, 𝑦 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ 〈(𝑥 / (2↑𝑦)), ((𝑥 + 1) / (2↑𝑦))〉) ∣ ([,]‘𝑏) ⊆ 𝐴} (([,]‘𝑎) ⊆ ([,]‘𝑐) → 𝑎 = 𝑐)}) | ||
Theorem | mblfinlem2 37618* | Lemma for ismblfin 37621, effectively one direction of the same fact for open sets, made necessary by Viaclovsky's slightly different definition of outer measure. Note that unlike the main theorem, this holds for sets of infinite measure. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Feb-2018.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 13-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (topGen‘ran (,)) ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝑀 < (vol*‘𝐴)) → ∃𝑠 ∈ (Clsd‘(topGen‘ran (,)))(𝑠 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑀 < (vol*‘𝑠))) | ||
Theorem | mblfinlem3 37619* | The difference between two sets measurable by the criterion in ismblfin 37621 is itself measurable by the same. Corollary 0.3 of [Viaclovsky7] p. 3. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 25-Mar-2018.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 13-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ⊆ ℝ ∧ (vol*‘𝐴) ∈ ℝ) ∧ (𝐵 ⊆ ℝ ∧ (vol*‘𝐵) ∈ ℝ) ∧ ((vol*‘𝐴) = sup({𝑦 ∣ ∃𝑏 ∈ (Clsd‘(topGen‘ran (,)))(𝑏 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = (vol‘𝑏))}, ℝ, < ) ∧ (vol*‘𝐵) = sup({𝑦 ∣ ∃𝑏 ∈ (Clsd‘(topGen‘ran (,)))(𝑏 ⊆ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑦 = (vol‘𝑏))}, ℝ, < ))) → sup({𝑦 ∣ ∃𝑏 ∈ (Clsd‘(topGen‘ran (,)))(𝑏 ⊆ (𝐴 ∖ 𝐵) ∧ 𝑦 = (vol‘𝑏))}, ℝ, < ) = (vol*‘(𝐴 ∖ 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | mblfinlem4 37620* | Backward direction of ismblfin 37621. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 28-Mar-2018.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 13-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ⊆ ℝ ∧ (vol*‘𝐴) ∈ ℝ) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ dom vol) → (vol*‘𝐴) = sup({𝑦 ∣ ∃𝑏 ∈ (Clsd‘(topGen‘ran (,)))(𝑏 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = (vol‘𝑏))}, ℝ, < )) | ||
Theorem | ismblfin 37621* | Measurability in terms of inner and outer measure. Proposition 7 of [Viaclovsky8] p. 3. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 4-Mar-2018.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 28-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ⊆ ℝ ∧ (vol*‘𝐴) ∈ ℝ) → (𝐴 ∈ dom vol ↔ (vol*‘𝐴) = sup({𝑦 ∣ ∃𝑏 ∈ (Clsd‘(topGen‘ran (,)))(𝑏 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = (vol‘𝑏))}, ℝ, < ))) | ||
Theorem | ovoliunnfl 37622* | ovoliun 25559 is incompatible with the Feferman-Levy model. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝑓 Fn ℕ ∧ ∀𝑛 ∈ ℕ ((𝑓‘𝑛) ⊆ ℝ ∧ (vol*‘(𝑓‘𝑛)) ∈ ℝ)) → (vol*‘∪ 𝑚 ∈ ℕ (𝑓‘𝑚)) ≤ sup(ran seq1( + , (𝑚 ∈ ℕ ↦ (vol*‘(𝑓‘𝑚)))), ℝ*, < )) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ ℕ ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥 ≼ ℕ) → ∪ 𝐴 ≠ ℝ) | ||
Theorem | ex-ovoliunnfl 37623* | Demonstration of ovoliunnfl 37622. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 21-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ ℕ ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥 ≼ ℕ) → ∪ 𝐴 ≠ ℝ) | ||
Theorem | voliunnfl 37624* | voliun 25608 is incompatible with the Feferman-Levy model; in that model, therefore, the Lebesgue measure as we've defined it isn't actually a measure. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 16-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = seq1( + , 𝐺) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑛 ∈ ℕ ↦ (vol‘(𝑓‘𝑛))) & ⊢ ((∀𝑛 ∈ ℕ ((𝑓‘𝑛) ∈ dom vol ∧ (vol‘(𝑓‘𝑛)) ∈ ℝ) ∧ Disj 𝑛 ∈ ℕ (𝑓‘𝑛)) → (vol‘∪ 𝑛 ∈ ℕ (𝑓‘𝑛)) = sup(ran 𝑆, ℝ*, < )) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ ℕ ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥 ≼ ℕ) → ∪ 𝐴 ≠ ℝ) | ||
Theorem | volsupnfl 37625* | volsup 25610 is incompatible with the Feferman-Levy model. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 2-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝑓:ℕ⟶dom vol ∧ ∀𝑛 ∈ ℕ (𝑓‘𝑛) ⊆ (𝑓‘(𝑛 + 1))) → (vol‘∪ ran 𝑓) = sup((vol “ ran 𝑓), ℝ*, < )) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ ℕ ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥 ≼ ℕ) → ∪ 𝐴 ≠ ℝ) | ||
Theorem | mbfresfi 37626* | Measurability of a piecewise function across arbitrarily many subsets. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 31-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝐴⟶ℂ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ Fin) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑠 ∈ 𝑆 (𝐹 ↾ 𝑠) ∈ MblFn) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∪ 𝑆 = 𝐴) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ MblFn) | ||
Theorem | mbfposadd 37627* | If the sum of two measurable functions is measurable, the sum of their nonnegative parts is measurable. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 2-Apr-2018.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ MblFn) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) ∈ MblFn) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐶 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐵 + 𝐶)) ∈ MblFn) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (if(0 ≤ 𝐵, 𝐵, 0) + if(0 ≤ 𝐶, 𝐶, 0))) ∈ MblFn) | ||
Theorem | cnambfre 37628 | A real-valued, a.e. continuous function is measurable. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 4-Apr-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝐹:𝐴⟶ℝ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ dom vol ∧ (vol*‘(𝐴 ∖ ((◡(((topGen‘ran (,)) ↾t 𝐴) CnP (topGen‘ran (,))) ∘ E ) “ {𝐹}))) = 0) → 𝐹 ∈ MblFn) | ||
Theorem | dvtanlem 37629 | Lemma for dvtan 37630- the domain of the tangent is open. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 8-Aug-2018.) (Proof shortened by OpenAI, 3-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (◡cos “ (ℂ ∖ {0})) ∈ (TopOpen‘ℂfld) | ||
Theorem | dvtan 37630 | Derivative of tangent. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 7-Aug-2018.) |
⊢ (ℂ D tan) = (𝑥 ∈ dom tan ↦ ((cos‘𝑥)↑-2)) | ||
Theorem | itg2addnclem 37631* | An alternate expression for the ∫2 integral that includes an arbitrarily small but strictly positive "buffer zone" wherever the simple function is nonzero. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 10-Oct-2017.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 10-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ 𝐿 = {𝑥 ∣ ∃𝑔 ∈ dom ∫1(∃𝑦 ∈ ℝ+ (𝑧 ∈ ℝ ↦ if((𝑔‘𝑧) = 0, 0, ((𝑔‘𝑧) + 𝑦))) ∘r ≤ 𝐹 ∧ 𝑥 = (∫1‘𝑔))} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹:ℝ⟶(0[,]+∞) → (∫2‘𝐹) = sup(𝐿, ℝ*, < )) | ||
Theorem | itg2addnclem2 37632* | Lemma for itg2addnc 37634. The function described is a simple function. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 29-Oct-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ MblFn) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ℝ⟶(0[,)+∞)) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ ℎ ∈ dom ∫1) ∧ 𝑣 ∈ ℝ+) → (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ if(((((⌊‘((𝐹‘𝑥) / (𝑣 / 3))) − 1) · (𝑣 / 3)) ≤ (ℎ‘𝑥) ∧ (ℎ‘𝑥) ≠ 0), (((⌊‘((𝐹‘𝑥) / (𝑣 / 3))) − 1) · (𝑣 / 3)), (ℎ‘𝑥))) ∈ dom ∫1) | ||
Theorem | itg2addnclem3 37633* | Lemma incomprehensible in isolation split off to shorten proof of itg2addnc 37634. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 11-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ MblFn) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ℝ⟶(0[,)+∞)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (∫2‘𝐹) ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐺:ℝ⟶(0[,)+∞)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (∫2‘𝐺) ∈ ℝ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃ℎ ∈ dom ∫1(∃𝑦 ∈ ℝ+ (𝑧 ∈ ℝ ↦ if((ℎ‘𝑧) = 0, 0, ((ℎ‘𝑧) + 𝑦))) ∘r ≤ (𝐹 ∘f + 𝐺) ∧ 𝑠 = (∫1‘ℎ)) → ∃𝑡∃𝑢(∃𝑓 ∈ dom ∫1∃𝑔 ∈ dom ∫1((∃𝑐 ∈ ℝ+ (𝑧 ∈ ℝ ↦ if((𝑓‘𝑧) = 0, 0, ((𝑓‘𝑧) + 𝑐))) ∘r ≤ 𝐹 ∧ 𝑡 = (∫1‘𝑓)) ∧ (∃𝑑 ∈ ℝ+ (𝑧 ∈ ℝ ↦ if((𝑔‘𝑧) = 0, 0, ((𝑔‘𝑧) + 𝑑))) ∘r ≤ 𝐺 ∧ 𝑢 = (∫1‘𝑔))) ∧ 𝑠 = (𝑡 + 𝑢)))) | ||
Theorem | itg2addnc 37634 | Alternate proof of itg2add 25814 using the "buffer zone" definition from the first lemma, in which every simple function in the set is divided into to by dividing its buffer by a third and finding the largest allowable function locked to a grid laid out in increments of the new, smaller buffer up to the original simple function. The measurability of this function follows from that of the augend, and subtracting it from the original simple function yields another simple function by i1fsub 25763, which is allowable by the fact that the grid must have a mark between one third and two thirds the original buffer. This has two advantages over the current approach: first, eliminating ax-cc 10504, and second, weakening the measurability hypothesis to only the augend. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 31-Oct-2017.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 13-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ MblFn) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ℝ⟶(0[,)+∞)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (∫2‘𝐹) ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐺:ℝ⟶(0[,)+∞)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (∫2‘𝐺) ∈ ℝ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∫2‘(𝐹 ∘f + 𝐺)) = ((∫2‘𝐹) + (∫2‘𝐺))) | ||
Theorem | itg2gt0cn 37635* | itg2gt0 25815 holds on functions continuous on an open interval in the absence of ax-cc 10504. The fourth hypothesis is made unnecessary by the continuity hypothesis. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 16-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 < 𝑌) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ℝ⟶(0[,)+∞)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ (𝑋(,)𝑌)) → 0 < (𝐹‘𝑥)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹 ↾ (𝑋(,)𝑌)) ∈ ((𝑋(,)𝑌)–cn→ℂ)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 0 < (∫2‘𝐹)) | ||
Theorem | ibladdnclem 37636* | Lemma for ibladdnc 37637; cf ibladdlem 25875, whose fifth hypothesis is rendered unnecessary by the weakened hypotheses of itg2addnc 37634. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 31-Oct-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐶 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐷 = (𝐵 + 𝐶)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ MblFn) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (∫2‘(𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ if((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 0 ≤ 𝐵), 𝐵, 0))) ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (∫2‘(𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ if((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 0 ≤ 𝐶), 𝐶, 0))) ∈ ℝ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∫2‘(𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ if((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 0 ≤ 𝐷), 𝐷, 0))) ∈ ℝ) | ||
Theorem | ibladdnc 37637* | Choice-free analogue of itgadd 25880. A measurability hypothesis is necessitated by the loss of mbfadd 25715; for large classes of functions, such as continuous functions, it should be relatively easy to show. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 1-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐵 + 𝐶)) ∈ MblFn) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐵 + 𝐶)) ∈ 𝐿1) | ||
Theorem | itgaddnclem1 37638* | Lemma for itgaddnc 37640; cf. itgaddlem1 25878. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 7-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐵 + 𝐶)) ∈ MblFn) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐶 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 0 ≤ 𝐵) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 0 ≤ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∫𝐴(𝐵 + 𝐶) d𝑥 = (∫𝐴𝐵 d𝑥 + ∫𝐴𝐶 d𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | itgaddnclem2 37639* | Lemma for itgaddnc 37640; cf. itgaddlem2 25879. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 10-Nov-2017.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 3-Apr-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐵 + 𝐶)) ∈ MblFn) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐶 ∈ ℝ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∫𝐴(𝐵 + 𝐶) d𝑥 = (∫𝐴𝐵 d𝑥 + ∫𝐴𝐶 d𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | itgaddnc 37640* | Choice-free analogue of itgadd 25880. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 11-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐵 + 𝐶)) ∈ MblFn) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∫𝐴(𝐵 + 𝐶) d𝑥 = (∫𝐴𝐵 d𝑥 + ∫𝐴𝐶 d𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | iblsubnc 37641* | Choice-free analogue of iblsub 25877. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 11-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐵 − 𝐶)) ∈ MblFn) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐵 − 𝐶)) ∈ 𝐿1) | ||
Theorem | itgsubnc 37642* | Choice-free analogue of itgsub 25881. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 11-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐵 − 𝐶)) ∈ MblFn) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∫𝐴(𝐵 − 𝐶) d𝑥 = (∫𝐴𝐵 d𝑥 − ∫𝐴𝐶 d𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | iblabsnclem 37643* | Lemma for iblabsnc 37644; cf. iblabslem 25883. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 7-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ if(𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, (abs‘(𝐹‘𝐵)), 0)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐹‘𝐵)) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐹‘𝐵) ∈ ℝ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐺 ∈ MblFn ∧ (∫2‘𝐺) ∈ ℝ)) | ||
Theorem | iblabsnc 37644* | Choice-free analogue of iblabs 25884. As with ibladdnc 37637, a measurability hypothesis is needed. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 7-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (abs‘𝐵)) ∈ MblFn) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (abs‘𝐵)) ∈ 𝐿1) | ||
Theorem | iblmulc2nc 37645* | Choice-free analogue of iblmulc2 25886. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 17-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ ℂ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐶 · 𝐵)) ∈ MblFn) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐶 · 𝐵)) ∈ 𝐿1) | ||
Theorem | itgmulc2nclem1 37646* | Lemma for itgmulc2nc 37648; cf. itgmulc2lem1 25887. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 17-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ ℂ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐶 · 𝐵)) ∈ MblFn) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 0 ≤ 𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 0 ≤ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐶 · ∫𝐴𝐵 d𝑥) = ∫𝐴(𝐶 · 𝐵) d𝑥) | ||
Theorem | itgmulc2nclem2 37647* | Lemma for itgmulc2nc 37648; cf. itgmulc2lem2 25888. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 19-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ ℂ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐶 · 𝐵)) ∈ MblFn) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐶 · ∫𝐴𝐵 d𝑥) = ∫𝐴(𝐶 · 𝐵) d𝑥) | ||
Theorem | itgmulc2nc 37648* | Choice-free analogue of itgmulc2 25889. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 19-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ ℂ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝐶 · 𝐵)) ∈ MblFn) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐶 · ∫𝐴𝐵 d𝑥) = ∫𝐴(𝐶 · 𝐵) d𝑥) | ||
Theorem | itgabsnc 37649* | Choice-free analogue of itgabs 25890. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 19-Nov-2017.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 19-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (abs‘𝐵)) ∈ MblFn) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ ((∗‘∫𝐴𝐵 d𝑥) · ⦋𝑦 / 𝑥⦌𝐵)) ∈ MblFn) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (abs‘∫𝐴𝐵 d𝑥) ≤ ∫𝐴(abs‘𝐵) d𝑥) | ||
Theorem | itggt0cn 37650* | itggt0 25899 holds for continuous functions in the absence of ax-cc 10504. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 16-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 < 𝑌) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ (𝑋(,)𝑌) ↦ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ (𝑋(,)𝑌)) → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ+) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ (𝑋(,)𝑌) ↦ 𝐵) ∈ ((𝑋(,)𝑌)–cn→ℂ)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 0 < ∫(𝑋(,)𝑌)𝐵 d𝑥) | ||
Theorem | ftc1cnnclem 37651* | Lemma for ftc1cnnc 37652; cf. ftc1lem4 26100. The stronger assumptions of ftc1cn 26104 are exploited to make use of weaker theorems. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 19-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵) ↦ ∫(𝐴(,)𝑥)(𝐹‘𝑡) d𝑡) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≤ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ ((𝐴(,)𝐵)–cn→ℂ)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑐 ∈ (𝐴(,)𝐵)) & ⊢ 𝐻 = (𝑧 ∈ ((𝐴[,]𝐵) ∖ {𝑐}) ↦ (((𝐺‘𝑧) − (𝐺‘𝑐)) / (𝑧 − 𝑐))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐸 ∈ ℝ+) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 ∈ ℝ+) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝐴(,)𝐵)) → ((abs‘(𝑦 − 𝑐)) < 𝑅 → (abs‘((𝐹‘𝑦) − (𝐹‘𝑐))) < 𝐸)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (abs‘(𝑋 − 𝑐)) < 𝑅) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑌 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (abs‘(𝑌 − 𝑐)) < 𝑅) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑋 < 𝑌) → (abs‘((((𝐺‘𝑌) − (𝐺‘𝑋)) / (𝑌 − 𝑋)) − (𝐹‘𝑐))) < 𝐸) | ||
Theorem | ftc1cnnc 37652* | Choice-free proof of ftc1cn 26104. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 20-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵) ↦ ∫(𝐴(,)𝑥)(𝐹‘𝑡) d𝑡) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≤ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ ((𝐴(,)𝐵)–cn→ℂ)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ 𝐿1) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (ℝ D 𝐺) = 𝐹) | ||
Theorem | ftc1anclem1 37653 | Lemma for ftc1anc 37661- the absolute value of a real-valued measurable function is measurable. Would be trivial with cncombf 25712, but this proof avoids ax-cc 10504. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 18-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝐹:𝐴⟶ℝ ∧ 𝐹 ∈ MblFn) → (abs ∘ 𝐹) ∈ MblFn) | ||
Theorem | ftc1anclem2 37654* | Lemma for ftc1anc 37661- restriction of an integrable function to the absolute value of its real or imaginary part. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 19-Jun-2018.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 8-Aug-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝐹:𝐴⟶ℂ ∧ 𝐹 ∈ 𝐿1 ∧ 𝐺 ∈ {ℜ, ℑ}) → (∫2‘(𝑡 ∈ ℝ ↦ if(𝑡 ∈ 𝐴, (abs‘(𝐺‘(𝐹‘𝑡))), 0))) ∈ ℝ) | ||
Theorem | ftc1anclem3 37655 | Lemma for ftc1anc 37661- the absolute value of the sum of a simple function and i times another simple function is itself a simple function. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 27-May-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ dom ∫1 ∧ 𝐺 ∈ dom ∫1) → (abs ∘ (𝐹 ∘f + ((ℝ × {i}) ∘f · 𝐺))) ∈ dom ∫1) | ||
Theorem | ftc1anclem4 37656* | Lemma for ftc1anc 37661. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 17-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ dom ∫1 ∧ 𝐺 ∈ 𝐿1 ∧ 𝐺:ℝ⟶ℝ) → (∫2‘(𝑡 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((𝐺‘𝑡) − (𝐹‘𝑡))))) ∈ ℝ) | ||
Theorem | ftc1anclem5 37657* | Lemma for ftc1anc 37661, the existence of a simple function the integral of whose pointwise difference from the function is less than a given positive real. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 17-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵) ↦ ∫(𝐴(,)𝑥)(𝐹‘𝑡) d𝑡) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≤ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(,)𝐵) ⊆ 𝐷) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐷 ⊆ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝐷⟶ℂ) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ ℝ+) → ∃𝑓 ∈ dom ∫1(∫2‘(𝑡 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((ℜ‘if(𝑡 ∈ 𝐷, (𝐹‘𝑡), 0)) − (𝑓‘𝑡))))) < 𝑌) | ||
Theorem | ftc1anclem6 37658* | Lemma for ftc1anc 37661- construction of simple functions within an arbitrary absolute distance of the given function. Similar to Lemma 565Ib of [Fremlin5] p. 218, but without Fremlin's additional step of converting the simple function into a continuous one, which is unnecessary to this lemma's use; also, two simple functions are used to allow for complex-valued 𝐹. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 31-May-2018.) |
⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵) ↦ ∫(𝐴(,)𝑥)(𝐹‘𝑡) d𝑡) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≤ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(,)𝐵) ⊆ 𝐷) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐷 ⊆ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝐷⟶ℂ) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ ℝ+) → ∃𝑓 ∈ dom ∫1∃𝑔 ∈ dom ∫1(∫2‘(𝑡 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘(if(𝑡 ∈ 𝐷, (𝐹‘𝑡), 0) − ((𝑓‘𝑡) + (i · (𝑔‘𝑡))))))) < 𝑌) | ||
Theorem | ftc1anclem7 37659* | Lemma for ftc1anc 37661. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 13-May-2018.) |
⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵) ↦ ∫(𝐴(,)𝑥)(𝐹‘𝑡) d𝑡) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≤ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(,)𝐵) ⊆ 𝐷) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐷 ⊆ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝐷⟶ℂ) ⇒ ⊢ (((((((𝜑 ∧ (𝑓 ∈ dom ∫1 ∧ 𝑔 ∈ dom ∫1)) ∧ (∫2‘(𝑡 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘(if(𝑡 ∈ 𝐷, (𝐹‘𝑡), 0) − ((𝑓‘𝑡) + (i · (𝑔‘𝑡))))))) < (𝑦 / 2)) ∧ ∃𝑟 ∈ (ran 𝑓 ∪ ran 𝑔)𝑟 ≠ 0) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ℝ+) ∧ (𝑢 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵) ∧ 𝑤 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵) ∧ 𝑢 ≤ 𝑤)) ∧ (abs‘(𝑤 − 𝑢)) < ((𝑦 / 2) / (2 · sup((abs “ (ran 𝑓 ∪ ran 𝑔)), ℝ, < )))) → ((∫2‘(𝑡 ∈ ℝ ↦ if(𝑡 ∈ (𝑢(,)𝑤), (abs‘((𝑓‘𝑡) + (i · (𝑔‘𝑡)))), 0))) + (∫2‘(𝑡 ∈ ℝ ↦ if(𝑡 ∈ (𝑢(,)𝑤), (abs‘((𝐹‘𝑡) − ((𝑓‘𝑡) + (i · (𝑔‘𝑡))))), 0)))) < ((𝑦 / 2) + (𝑦 / 2))) | ||
Theorem | ftc1anclem8 37660* | Lemma for ftc1anc 37661. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 29-May-2018.) |
⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵) ↦ ∫(𝐴(,)𝑥)(𝐹‘𝑡) d𝑡) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≤ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(,)𝐵) ⊆ 𝐷) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐷 ⊆ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝐷⟶ℂ) ⇒ ⊢ (((((((𝜑 ∧ (𝑓 ∈ dom ∫1 ∧ 𝑔 ∈ dom ∫1)) ∧ (∫2‘(𝑡 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘(if(𝑡 ∈ 𝐷, (𝐹‘𝑡), 0) − ((𝑓‘𝑡) + (i · (𝑔‘𝑡))))))) < (𝑦 / 2)) ∧ ∃𝑟 ∈ (ran 𝑓 ∪ ran 𝑔)𝑟 ≠ 0) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ℝ+) ∧ (𝑢 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵) ∧ 𝑤 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵) ∧ 𝑢 ≤ 𝑤)) ∧ (abs‘(𝑤 − 𝑢)) < ((𝑦 / 2) / (2 · sup((abs “ (ran 𝑓 ∪ ran 𝑔)), ℝ, < )))) → (∫2‘(𝑡 ∈ ℝ ↦ if(𝑡 ∈ (𝑢(,)𝑤), ((abs‘((𝐹‘𝑡) − ((𝑓‘𝑡) + (i · (𝑔‘𝑡))))) + (abs‘((𝑓‘𝑡) + (i · (𝑔‘𝑡))))), 0))) < 𝑦) | ||
Theorem | ftc1anc 37661* | ftc1a 26098 holds for functions that obey the triangle inequality in the absence of ax-cc 10504. Theorem 565Ma of [Fremlin5] p. 220. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 11-May-2018.) |
⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴[,]𝐵) ↦ ∫(𝐴(,)𝑥)(𝐹‘𝑡) d𝑡) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≤ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(,)𝐵) ⊆ 𝐷) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐷 ⊆ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝐷⟶ℂ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑠 ∈ ((,) “ ((𝐴[,]𝐵) × (𝐴[,]𝐵)))(abs‘∫𝑠(𝐹‘𝑡) d𝑡) ≤ (∫2‘(𝑡 ∈ ℝ ↦ if(𝑡 ∈ 𝑠, (abs‘(𝐹‘𝑡)), 0)))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐺 ∈ ((𝐴[,]𝐵)–cn→ℂ)) | ||
Theorem | ftc2nc 37662* | Choice-free proof of ftc2 26105. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 19-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≤ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (ℝ D 𝐹) ∈ ((𝐴(,)𝐵)–cn→ℂ)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (ℝ D 𝐹) ∈ 𝐿1) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ ((𝐴[,]𝐵)–cn→ℂ)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∫(𝐴(,)𝐵)((ℝ D 𝐹)‘𝑡) d𝑡 = ((𝐹‘𝐵) − (𝐹‘𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | asindmre 37663 | Real part of domain of differentiability of arcsine. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 19-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ 𝐷 = (ℂ ∖ ((-∞(,]-1) ∪ (1[,)+∞))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐷 ∩ ℝ) = (-1(,)1) | ||
Theorem | dvasin 37664* | Derivative of arcsine. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 18-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ 𝐷 = (ℂ ∖ ((-∞(,]-1) ∪ (1[,)+∞))) ⇒ ⊢ (ℂ D (arcsin ↾ 𝐷)) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐷 ↦ (1 / (√‘(1 − (𝑥↑2))))) | ||
Theorem | dvacos 37665* | Derivative of arccosine. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 18-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ 𝐷 = (ℂ ∖ ((-∞(,]-1) ∪ (1[,)+∞))) ⇒ ⊢ (ℂ D (arccos ↾ 𝐷)) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐷 ↦ (-1 / (√‘(1 − (𝑥↑2))))) | ||
Theorem | dvreasin 37666 | Real derivative of arcsine. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 3-Aug-2017.) (Proof shortened by Brendan Leahy, 18-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ (ℝ D (arcsin ↾ (-1(,)1))) = (𝑥 ∈ (-1(,)1) ↦ (1 / (√‘(1 − (𝑥↑2))))) | ||
Theorem | dvreacos 37667 | Real derivative of arccosine. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 3-Aug-2017.) (Proof shortened by Brendan Leahy, 18-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ (ℝ D (arccos ↾ (-1(,)1))) = (𝑥 ∈ (-1(,)1) ↦ (-1 / (√‘(1 − (𝑥↑2))))) | ||
Theorem | areacirclem1 37668* | Antiderivative of cross-section of circle. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 28-Aug-2017.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 11-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ ℝ+ → (ℝ D (𝑡 ∈ (-𝑅(,)𝑅) ↦ ((𝑅↑2) · ((arcsin‘(𝑡 / 𝑅)) + ((𝑡 / 𝑅) · (√‘(1 − ((𝑡 / 𝑅)↑2)))))))) = (𝑡 ∈ (-𝑅(,)𝑅) ↦ (2 · (√‘((𝑅↑2) − (𝑡↑2)))))) | ||
Theorem | areacirclem2 37669* | Endpoint-inclusive continuity of Cartesian ordinate of circle. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 29-Aug-2017.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 11-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ ℝ ∧ 0 ≤ 𝑅) → (𝑡 ∈ (-𝑅[,]𝑅) ↦ (√‘((𝑅↑2) − (𝑡↑2)))) ∈ ((-𝑅[,]𝑅)–cn→ℂ)) | ||
Theorem | areacirclem3 37670* | Integrability of cross-section of circle. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 26-Aug-2017.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 11-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ ℝ ∧ 0 ≤ 𝑅) → (𝑡 ∈ (-𝑅[,]𝑅) ↦ (2 · (√‘((𝑅↑2) − (𝑡↑2))))) ∈ 𝐿1) | ||
Theorem | areacirclem4 37671* | Endpoint-inclusive continuity of antiderivative of cross-section of circle. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 31-Aug-2017.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 11-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ ℝ+ → (𝑡 ∈ (-𝑅[,]𝑅) ↦ ((𝑅↑2) · ((arcsin‘(𝑡 / 𝑅)) + ((𝑡 / 𝑅) · (√‘(1 − ((𝑡 / 𝑅)↑2))))))) ∈ ((-𝑅[,]𝑅)–cn→ℂ)) | ||
Theorem | areacirclem5 37672* | Finding the cross-section of a circle. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 31-Aug-2017.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 22-Sep-2017.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 11-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ℝ) ∧ ((𝑥↑2) + (𝑦↑2)) ≤ (𝑅↑2))} ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ ℝ ∧ 0 ≤ 𝑅 ∧ 𝑡 ∈ ℝ) → (𝑆 “ {𝑡}) = if((abs‘𝑡) ≤ 𝑅, (-(√‘((𝑅↑2) − (𝑡↑2)))[,](√‘((𝑅↑2) − (𝑡↑2)))), ∅)) | ||
Theorem | areacirc 37673* | The area of a circle of radius 𝑅 is π · 𝑅↑2. This is Metamath 100 proof #9. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 31-Aug-2017.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 22-Sep-2017.) (Revised by Brendan Leahy, 11-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ ℝ ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ℝ) ∧ ((𝑥↑2) + (𝑦↑2)) ≤ (𝑅↑2))} ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ ℝ ∧ 0 ≤ 𝑅) → (area‘𝑆) = (π · (𝑅↑2))) | ||
Theorem | unirep 37674* | Define a quantity whose definition involves a choice of representative, but which is uniquely determined regardless of the choice. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 1-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐷 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐷 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑧 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑧 → 𝐵 = 𝐹) & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝐵 = 𝐹) ∧ (𝐷 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝜓)) → (℩𝑥∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐵)) = 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | cover2 37675* | Two ways of expressing the statement "there is a cover of 𝐴 by elements of 𝐵 such that for each set in the cover, 𝜑". Note that 𝜑 and 𝑥 must be distinct. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 20-Jun-2010.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐴 = ∪ 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝒫 𝐵(∪ 𝑧 = 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | cover2g 37676* | Two ways of expressing the statement "there is a cover of 𝐴 by elements of 𝐵 such that for each set in the cover, 𝜑". Note that 𝜑 and 𝑥 must be distinct. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 21-Jun-2010.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = ∪ 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 → (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝒫 𝐵(∪ 𝑧 = 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | brabg2 37677* | Relation by a binary relation abstraction. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ 𝑅 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐷 → (𝐴𝑅𝐵 ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | opelopab3 37678* | Ordered pair membership in an ordered pair class abstraction, with a reduced hypothesis. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 29-May-2011.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐷 → (〈𝐴, 𝐵〉 ∈ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | cocanfo 37679 | Cancellation of a surjective function from the right side of a composition. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 1-Jun-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 27-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝐹:𝐴–onto→𝐵 ∧ 𝐺 Fn 𝐵 ∧ 𝐻 Fn 𝐵) ∧ (𝐺 ∘ 𝐹) = (𝐻 ∘ 𝐹)) → 𝐺 = 𝐻) | ||
Theorem | brresi2 37680 | Restriction of a binary relation. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴(𝑅 ↾ 𝐶)𝐵 → 𝐴𝑅𝐵) | ||
Theorem | fnopabeqd 37681* | Equality deduction for function abstractions. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 19-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵)} = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐶)}) | ||
Theorem | fvopabf4g 37682* | Function value of an operator abstraction whose domain is a set of functions with given domain and range. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 1-Dec-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝑅 ↑m 𝐷) ↦ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝑅 ∈ 𝑌 ∧ 𝐴:𝐷⟶𝑅) → (𝐹‘𝐴) = 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | fnopabco 37683* | Composition of a function with a function abstraction. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 27-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶) & ⊢ 𝐹 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵)} & ⊢ 𝐺 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = (𝐻‘𝐵))} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐻 Fn 𝐶 → 𝐺 = (𝐻 ∘ 𝐹)) | ||
Theorem | opropabco 37684* | Composition of an operator with a function abstraction. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 11-Jun-2010.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑅) & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑆) & ⊢ 𝐹 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 〈𝐵, 𝐶〉)} & ⊢ 𝐺 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = (𝐵𝑀𝐶))} ⇒ ⊢ (𝑀 Fn (𝑅 × 𝑆) → 𝐺 = (𝑀 ∘ 𝐹)) | ||
Theorem | cocnv 37685 | Composition with a function and then with the converse. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ Fun 𝐺) → ((𝐹 ∘ 𝐺) ∘ ◡𝐺) = (𝐹 ↾ ran 𝐺)) | ||
Theorem | f1ocan1fv 37686 | Cancel a composition by a bijection by preapplying the converse. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 27-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐺:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝐵) → ((𝐹 ∘ 𝐺)‘(◡𝐺‘𝑋)) = (𝐹‘𝑋)) | ||
Theorem | f1ocan2fv 37687 | Cancel a composition by the converse of a bijection by preapplying the bijection. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐺:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝐴) → ((𝐹 ∘ ◡𝐺)‘(𝐺‘𝑋)) = (𝐹‘𝑋)) | ||
Theorem | inixp 37688* | Intersection of Cartesian products over the same base set. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ (X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∩ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶) = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐵 ∩ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | upixp 37689* | Universal property of the indexed Cartesian product. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 12-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = X𝑏 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐶‘𝑏) & ⊢ 𝑃 = (𝑤 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ↦ (𝑥‘𝑤))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑅 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ ∀𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐹‘𝑎):𝐵⟶(𝐶‘𝑎)) → ∃!ℎ(ℎ:𝐵⟶𝑋 ∧ ∀𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐹‘𝑎) = ((𝑃‘𝑎) ∘ ℎ))) | ||
Theorem | abrexdom 37690* | An indexed set is dominated by the indexing set. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 → ∃*𝑥𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝑥 ∣ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑} ≼ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | abrexdom2 37691* | An indexed set is dominated by the indexing set. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝑥 ∣ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥 = 𝐵} ≼ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ac6gf 37692* | Axiom of Choice. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑦 = (𝑓‘𝑥) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑) → ∃𝑓(𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | indexa 37693* | If for every element of an indexing set 𝐴 there exists a corresponding element of another set 𝐵, then there exists a subset of 𝐵 consisting only of those elements which are indexed by 𝐴. Used to avoid the Axiom of Choice in situations where only the range of the choice function is needed. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝑀 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑) → ∃𝑐(𝑐 ⊆ 𝐵 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑐 𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑐 ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | indexdom 37694* | If for every element of an indexing set 𝐴 there exists a corresponding element of another set 𝐵, then there exists a subset of 𝐵 consisting only of those elements which are indexed by 𝐴, and which is dominated by the set 𝐴. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑀 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑) → ∃𝑐((𝑐 ≼ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑐 ⊆ 𝐵) ∧ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑐 𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑐 ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | frinfm 37695* | A subset of a well-founded set has an infimum. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅)) → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ¬ 𝑥◡𝑅𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑦◡𝑅𝑥 → ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝐵 𝑦◡𝑅𝑧))) | ||
Theorem | welb 37696* | A nonempty subset of a well-ordered set has a lower bound. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 We 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅)) → (◡𝑅 Or 𝐵 ∧ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 (∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ¬ 𝑥◡𝑅𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑦◡𝑅𝑥 → ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝐵 𝑦◡𝑅𝑧)))) | ||
Theorem | supex2g 37697 | Existence of supremum. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 → sup(𝐵, 𝐴, 𝑅) ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | supclt 37698* | Closure of supremum. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ¬ 𝑥𝑅𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑦𝑅𝑥 → ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝐵 𝑦𝑅𝑧))) → sup(𝐵, 𝐴, 𝑅) ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | supubt 37699* | Upper bound property of supremum. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ¬ 𝑥𝑅𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑦𝑅𝑥 → ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝐵 𝑦𝑅𝑧))) → (𝐶 ∈ 𝐵 → ¬ sup(𝐵, 𝐴, 𝑅)𝑅𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | filbcmb 37700* | Combine a finite set of lower bounds. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅ ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ ℝ) → (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑦 ≤ 𝑧 → 𝜑) → ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑦 ≤ 𝑧 → ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑))) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |