HomeHome Metamath Proof Explorer
Theorem List (p. 464 of 464)
< Previous  Wrap >
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version.

Mirrors  >  Metamath Home Page  >  MPE Home Page  >  Theorem List Contents  >  Recent Proofs       This page: Page List

Color key:    Metamath Proof Explorer  Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29156)
  Hilbert Space Explorer  Hilbert Space Explorer
(29157-30679)
  Users' Mathboxes  Users' Mathboxes
(30680-46368)
 

Theorem List for Metamath Proof Explorer - 46301-46368   *Has distinct variable group(s)
TypeLabelDescription
Statement
 
Theoremsinhpcosh 46301 Prove that (sinh‘𝐴) + (cosh‘𝐴) = (exp‘𝐴) using the conventional hyperbolic trigonometric functions. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 27-May-2015.)
(𝐴 ∈ ℂ → ((sinh‘𝐴) + (cosh‘𝐴)) = (exp‘𝐴))
 
20.44.4  Reciprocal trigonometric functions (sec, csc, cot)

Define the traditional reciprocal trigonometric functions secant (sec), cosecant (csc), and cotangent (cos), along with various identities involving them.

 
Syntaxcsec 46302 Extend class notation to include the secant function, see df-sec 46305.
class sec
 
Syntaxccsc 46303 Extend class notation to include the cosecant function, see df-csc 46306.
class csc
 
Syntaxccot 46304 Extend class notation to include the cotangent function, see df-cot 46307.
class cot
 
Definitiondf-sec 46305* Define the secant function. We define it this way for cmpt 5152, which requires the form (𝑥𝐴𝐵). The sec function is defined in ISO 80000-2:2009(E) operation 2-13.6 and "NIST Digital Library of Mathematical Functions" section on "Trigonometric Functions" http://dlmf.nist.gov/4.14 5152. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 14-Mar-2014.)
sec = (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∈ ℂ ∣ (cos‘𝑦) ≠ 0} ↦ (1 / (cos‘𝑥)))
 
Definitiondf-csc 46306* Define the cosecant function. We define it this way for cmpt 5152, which requires the form (𝑥𝐴𝐵). The csc function is defined in ISO 80000-2:2009(E) operation 2-13.7 and "NIST Digital Library of Mathematical Functions" section on "Trigonometric Functions" http://dlmf.nist.gov/4.14 5152. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 14-Mar-2014.)
csc = (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∈ ℂ ∣ (sin‘𝑦) ≠ 0} ↦ (1 / (sin‘𝑥)))
 
Definitiondf-cot 46307* Define the cotangent function. We define it this way for cmpt 5152, which requires the form (𝑥𝐴𝐵). The cot function is defined in ISO 80000-2:2009(E) operation 2-13.5 and "NIST Digital Library of Mathematical Functions" section on "Trigonometric Functions" http://dlmf.nist.gov/4.14 5152. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 14-Mar-2014.)
cot = (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∈ ℂ ∣ (sin‘𝑦) ≠ 0} ↦ ((cos‘𝑥) / (sin‘𝑥)))
 
Theoremsecval 46308 Value of the secant function. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 14-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ (cos‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (sec‘𝐴) = (1 / (cos‘𝐴)))
 
Theoremcscval 46309 Value of the cosecant function. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 14-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ (sin‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (csc‘𝐴) = (1 / (sin‘𝐴)))
 
Theoremcotval 46310 Value of the cotangent function. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 14-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ (sin‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (cot‘𝐴) = ((cos‘𝐴) / (sin‘𝐴)))
 
Theoremseccl 46311 The closure of the secant function with a complex argument. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 14-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ (cos‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (sec‘𝐴) ∈ ℂ)
 
Theoremcsccl 46312 The closure of the cosecant function with a complex argument. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 14-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ (sin‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (csc‘𝐴) ∈ ℂ)
 
Theoremcotcl 46313 The closure of the cotangent function with a complex argument. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 15-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ (sin‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (cot‘𝐴) ∈ ℂ)
 
Theoremreseccl 46314 The closure of the secant function with a real argument. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 15-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℝ ∧ (cos‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (sec‘𝐴) ∈ ℝ)
 
Theoremrecsccl 46315 The closure of the cosecant function with a real argument. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 15-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℝ ∧ (sin‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (csc‘𝐴) ∈ ℝ)
 
Theoremrecotcl 46316 The closure of the cotangent function with a real argument. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 15-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℝ ∧ (sin‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (cot‘𝐴) ∈ ℝ)
 
Theoremrecsec 46317 The reciprocal of secant is cosine. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 14-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ (cos‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (cos‘𝐴) = (1 / (sec‘𝐴)))
 
Theoremreccsc 46318 The reciprocal of cosecant is sine. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 14-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ (sin‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (sin‘𝐴) = (1 / (csc‘𝐴)))
 
Theoremreccot 46319 The reciprocal of cotangent is tangent. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 21-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ (sin‘𝐴) ≠ 0 ∧ (cos‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (tan‘𝐴) = (1 / (cot‘𝐴)))
 
Theoremrectan 46320 The reciprocal of tangent is cotangent. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 21-Mar-2014.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ (sin‘𝐴) ≠ 0 ∧ (cos‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (cot‘𝐴) = (1 / (tan‘𝐴)))
 
Theoremsec0 46321 The value of the secant function at zero is one. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 16-Mar-2014.)
(sec‘0) = 1
 
Theoremonetansqsecsq 46322 Prove the tangent squared secant squared identity (1 + ((tan A ) ^ 2 ) ) = ( ( sec 𝐴)↑2)). (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 25-May-2015.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ (cos‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (1 + ((tan‘𝐴)↑2)) = ((sec‘𝐴)↑2))
 
Theoremcotsqcscsq 46323 Prove the tangent squared cosecant squared identity (1 + ((cot A ) ^ 2 ) ) = ( ( csc 𝐴)↑2)). (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 27-May-2015.)
((𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ (sin‘𝐴) ≠ 0) → (1 + ((cot‘𝐴)↑2)) = ((csc‘𝐴)↑2))
 
20.44.5  Identities for "if"

Utility theorems for "if".

 
Theoremifnmfalse 46324 If A is not a member of B, but an "if" condition requires it, then the "false" branch results. This is a simple utility to provide a slight shortening and simplification of proofs versus applying iffalse 4465 directly in this case. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 15-May-2015.)
(𝐴𝐵 → if(𝐴𝐵, 𝐶, 𝐷) = 𝐷)
 
20.44.6  Logarithms generalized to arbitrary base using ` logb `

Most of this subsection was moved to main set.mm, section "Logarithms to an arbitrary base".

 
Theoremlogb2aval 46325 Define the value of the logb function, the logarithm generalized to an arbitrary base, when used in the 2-argument form logb𝐵, 𝑋 (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 21-Jan-2017.) (Revised by David A. Wheeler, 16-Jul-2017.)
((𝐵 ∈ (ℂ ∖ {0, 1}) ∧ 𝑋 ∈ (ℂ ∖ {0})) → ( logb ‘⟨𝐵, 𝑋⟩) = ((log‘𝑋) / (log‘𝐵)))
 
20.44.7  Logarithm laws generalized to an arbitrary base - log_

Define "log using an arbitrary base" function and then prove some of its properties. This builds on previous work by Stefan O'Rear.

This supports the notational form ((log_‘𝐵)‘𝑋); that looks a little more like traditional notation, but is different from other 2-parameter functions. E.g., ((log_‘10)‘100) = 2.

This form is less convenient to work with inside set.mm as compared to the (𝐵 logb 𝑋) form defined separately.

 
Syntaxclog- 46326 Extend class notation to include the logarithm generalized to an arbitrary base.
class log_
 
Definitiondf-logbALT 46327* Define the log_ operator. This is the logarithm generalized to an arbitrary base. It can be used as ((log_‘𝐵)‘𝑋) for "log base B of X". This formulation suggested by Mario Carneiro. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 14-Jul-2017.) (New usage is discouraged.)
log_ = (𝑏 ∈ (ℂ ∖ {0, 1}) ↦ (𝑥 ∈ (ℂ ∖ {0}) ↦ ((log‘𝑥) / (log‘𝑏))))
 
20.44.8  Formally define notions such as reflexivity

EXPERIMENTAL. Several terms are used in comments but not directly defined in set.mm. For example, there are proofs that a number of specific relations are reflexive, but there is no formal definition of what being reflexive actually *means*. Stating the relationships directly, instead of defining a broader property such as being reflexive, can reduce proof size (because the definition of that property does not need to be expanded later). A disadvantage, however, is that there are several terms that are widely used in comments but do not have a clear formal definition.

Here we define wffs that formally define some of these key terms. The intent isn't to use these directly, but to instead provide a clear formal definition of widely-used mathematical terminology (we even use this terminology within the comments of set.mm itself).

We could define these using extensible structures, but doing so appears overly restrictive. These definitions don't require the use of extensible structures; requiring something to be in an extensible structure to use them is too restrictive. Even if an extensible structure is already in use, it may in use for other things. For example, in geometry, there is a "less-than" relation, but while the geometry itself is an extensible structure, we would have to build a new structure to state "the geometric less-than relation is transitive" (which is more work than it's probably worth). By creating definitions that aren't tied to extensible structures we create definitions that can be applied to anything, including extensible structures, in whatever way we'd like.

BJ suggests that it might be better to define these as functions. There are many advantages to doing that, but they won't work for proper classes. I'm currently trying to also support proper classes, so I have not taken that approach, but if that turns out to be unreasonable then BJ's approach is very much worth considering. Examples would be: BinRel = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ {𝑟𝑟 ⊆ (𝑥 × 𝑥)}), ReflBinRel = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ {𝑟 ∈ ( BinRel 𝑥) ∣ ( I ↾ 𝑥) ⊆ 𝑟}), and IrreflBinRel = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ {𝑟 ∈ ( BinRel 𝑥) ∣ (𝑟 ∩ ( I ↾ 𝑥)) = ∅}).

For more discussion see: https://github.com/metamath/set.mm/pull/1286

 
Syntaxwreflexive 46328 Extend wff definition to include "Reflexive" applied to a class, which is true iff class R is a reflexive relation over the set A. See df-reflexive 46329. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 1-Dec-2019.)
wff 𝑅Reflexive𝐴
 
Definitiondf-reflexive 46329* Define reflexive relation; relation 𝑅 is reflexive over the set 𝐴 iff 𝑥𝐴𝑥𝑅𝑥. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 1-Dec-2019.)
(𝑅Reflexive𝐴 ↔ (𝑅 ⊆ (𝐴 × 𝐴) ∧ ∀𝑥𝐴 𝑥𝑅𝑥))
 
Syntaxwirreflexive 46330 Extend wff definition to include "Irreflexive" applied to a class, which is true iff class R is an irreflexive relation over the set A. See df-irreflexive 46331. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 1-Dec-2019.)
wff 𝑅Irreflexive𝐴
 
Definitiondf-irreflexive 46331* Define irreflexive relation; relation 𝑅 is irreflexive over the set 𝐴 iff 𝑥𝐴¬ 𝑥𝑅𝑥. Note that a relation can be neither reflexive nor irreflexive. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 1-Dec-2019.)
(𝑅Irreflexive𝐴 ↔ (𝑅 ⊆ (𝐴 × 𝐴) ∧ ∀𝑥𝐴 ¬ 𝑥𝑅𝑥))
 
20.44.9  Algebra helpers

This is an experimental approach to make it clearer (and easier) to do basic algebra in set.mm.

These little theorems support basic algebra on equations at a slightly higher conceptual level. Instead of always having to "build up" equivalent expressions for one side of an equation, these theorems allow you to directly manipulate an equality. These higher-level steps lead to easier to understand proofs when they can be used, as well as proofs that are slightly shorter (when measured in steps).

There are disadvantages. In particular, this approach requires many theorems (for many permutations to provide all of the operations). It can also only handle certain cases; more complex approaches must still be approached by "building up" equalities as is done today.

However, I expect that we can create enough theorems to make it worth doing. I'm trying this out to see if this is helpful and if the number of permutations is manageable.

To commute LHS for addition, use addcomli 11072. We might want to switch to a naming convention like addcomli 11072.

 
Theoremcomraddi 46332 Commute RHS addition. See addcomli 11072 to commute addition on LHS. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 11-Oct-2018.)
𝐵 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐶 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐴 = (𝐵 + 𝐶)       𝐴 = (𝐶 + 𝐵)
 
Theoremmvlraddi 46333 Move the right term in a sum on the LHS to the RHS. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 11-Oct-2018.)
𝐴 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐵 ∈ ℂ    &   (𝐴 + 𝐵) = 𝐶       𝐴 = (𝐶𝐵)
 
Theoremmvrladdi 46334 Move the left term in a sum on the RHS to the LHS. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 11-Oct-2018.)
𝐵 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐶 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐴 = (𝐵 + 𝐶)       (𝐴𝐵) = 𝐶
 
Theoremassraddsubi 46335 Associate RHS addition-subtraction. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 11-Oct-2018.)
𝐵 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐶 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐷 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐴 = ((𝐵 + 𝐶) − 𝐷)       𝐴 = (𝐵 + (𝐶𝐷))
 
Theoremjoinlmuladdmuli 46336 Join AB+CB into (A+C) on LHS. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 26-Oct-2019.)
𝐴 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐵 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐶 ∈ ℂ    &   ((𝐴 · 𝐵) + (𝐶 · 𝐵)) = 𝐷       ((𝐴 + 𝐶) · 𝐵) = 𝐷
 
Theoremjoinlmulsubmuld 46337 Join AB-CB into (A-C) on LHS. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 15-Oct-2018.)
(𝜑𝐴 ∈ ℂ)    &   (𝜑𝐵 ∈ ℂ)    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ ℂ)    &   (𝜑 → ((𝐴 · 𝐵) − (𝐶 · 𝐵)) = 𝐷)       (𝜑 → ((𝐴𝐶) · 𝐵) = 𝐷)
 
Theoremjoinlmulsubmuli 46338 Join AB-CB into (A-C) on LHS. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 11-Oct-2018.)
𝐴 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐵 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐶 ∈ ℂ    &   ((𝐴 · 𝐵) − (𝐶 · 𝐵)) = 𝐷       ((𝐴𝐶) · 𝐵) = 𝐷
 
Theoremmvlrmuld 46339 Move the right term in a product on the LHS to the RHS, deduction form. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 11-Oct-2018.)
(𝜑𝐴 ∈ ℂ)    &   (𝜑𝐵 ∈ ℂ)    &   (𝜑𝐵 ≠ 0)    &   (𝜑 → (𝐴 · 𝐵) = 𝐶)       (𝜑𝐴 = (𝐶 / 𝐵))
 
Theoremmvlrmuli 46340 Move the right term in a product on the LHS to the RHS, inference form. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 11-Oct-2018.)
𝐴 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐵 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐵 ≠ 0    &   (𝐴 · 𝐵) = 𝐶       𝐴 = (𝐶 / 𝐵)
 
20.44.10  Algebra helper examples

Examples using the algebra helpers.

 
Theoremi2linesi 46341 Solve for the intersection of two lines expressed in Y = MX+B form (note that the lines cannot be vertical). Here we use inference form. We just solve for X, since Y can be trivially found by using X. This is an example of how to use the algebra helpers. Notice that because this proof uses algebra helpers, the main steps of the proof are higher level and easier to follow by a human reader. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 11-Oct-2018.)
𝐴 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐵 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐶 ∈ ℂ    &   𝐷 ∈ ℂ    &   𝑋 ∈ ℂ    &   𝑌 = ((𝐴 · 𝑋) + 𝐵)    &   𝑌 = ((𝐶 · 𝑋) + 𝐷)    &   (𝐴𝐶) ≠ 0       𝑋 = ((𝐷𝐵) / (𝐴𝐶))
 
Theoremi2linesd 46342 Solve for the intersection of two lines expressed in Y = MX+B form (note that the lines cannot be vertical). Here we use deduction form. We just solve for X, since Y can be trivially found by using X. This is an example of how to use the algebra helpers. Notice that because this proof uses algebra helpers, the main steps of the proof are higher level and easier to follow by a human reader. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 15-Oct-2018.)
(𝜑𝐴 ∈ ℂ)    &   (𝜑𝐵 ∈ ℂ)    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ ℂ)    &   (𝜑𝐷 ∈ ℂ)    &   (𝜑𝑋 ∈ ℂ)    &   (𝜑𝑌 = ((𝐴 · 𝑋) + 𝐵))    &   (𝜑𝑌 = ((𝐶 · 𝑋) + 𝐷))    &   (𝜑 → (𝐴𝐶) ≠ 0)       (𝜑𝑋 = ((𝐷𝐵) / (𝐴𝐶)))
 
20.44.11  Formal methods "surprises"

Prove that some formal expressions using classical logic have meanings that might not be obvious to some lay readers. I find these are common mistakes and are worth pointing out to new people. In particular we prove alimp-surprise 46343, empty-surprise 46345, and eximp-surprise 46347.

 
Theoremalimp-surprise 46343 Demonstrate that when using "for all" and material implication the consequent can be both always true and always false if there is no case where the antecedent is true.

Those inexperienced with formal notations of classical logic can be surprised with what "for all" and material implication do together when the implication's antecedent is never true. This can happen, for example, when the antecedent is set membership but the set is the empty set (e.g., 𝑥𝑀 and 𝑀 = ∅).

This is perhaps best explained using an example. The sentence "All Martians are green" would typically be represented formally using the expression 𝑥(𝜑𝜓). In this expression 𝜑 is true iff 𝑥 is a Martian and 𝜓 is true iff 𝑥 is green. Similarly, "All Martians are not green" would typically be represented as 𝑥(𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓). However, if there are no Martians (¬ ∃𝑥𝜑), then both of those expressions are true. That is surprising to the inexperienced, because the two expressions seem to be the opposite of each other. The reason this occurs is because in classical logic the implication (𝜑𝜓) is equivalent to ¬ 𝜑𝜓 (as proven in imor 853). When 𝜑 is always false, ¬ 𝜑 is always true, and an or with true is always true.

Here are a few technical notes. In this notation, 𝜑 and 𝜓 are predicates that return a true or false value and may depend on 𝑥. We only say may because it actually doesn't matter for our proof. In Metamath this simply means that we do not require that 𝜑, 𝜓, and 𝑥 be distinct (so 𝑥 can be part of 𝜑 or 𝜓).

In natural language the term "implies" often presumes that the antecedent can occur in at one least circumstance and that there is some sort of causality. However, exactly what causality means is complex and situation-dependent. Modern logic typically uses material implication instead; this has a rigorous definition, but it is important for new users of formal notation to precisely understand it. There are ways to solve this, e.g., expressly stating that the antecedent exists (see alimp-no-surprise 46344) or using the allsome quantifier (df-alsi 46351) .

For other "surprises" for new users of classical logic, see empty-surprise 46345 and eximp-surprise 46347. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 17-Oct-2018.)

¬ ∃𝑥𝜑       (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ∧ ∀𝑥(𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓))
 
Theoremalimp-no-surprise 46344 There is no "surprise" in a for-all with implication if there exists a value where the antecedent is true. This is one way to prevent for-all with implication from allowing anything. For a contrast, see alimp-surprise 46343. The allsome quantifier also counters this problem, see df-alsi 46351. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 27-Oct-2018.)
¬ (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ∧ ∀𝑥(𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) ∧ ∃𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremempty-surprise 46345 Demonstrate that when using restricted "for all" over a class the expression can be both always true and always false if the class is empty.

Those inexperienced with formal notations of classical logic can be surprised with what restricted "for all" does over an empty set. It is important to note that 𝑥𝐴𝜑 is simply an abbreviation for 𝑥(𝑥𝐴𝜑) (per df-ral 3069). Thus, if 𝐴 is the empty set, this expression is always true regardless of the value of 𝜑 (see alimp-surprise 46343).

If you want the expression 𝑥𝐴𝜑 to not be vacuously true, you need to ensure that set 𝐴 is inhabited (e.g., 𝑥𝐴). (Technical note: You can also assert that 𝐴 ≠ ∅; this is an equivalent claim in classical logic as proven in n0 4278, but in intuitionistic logic the statement 𝐴 ≠ ∅ is a weaker claim than 𝑥𝐴.)

Some materials on logic (particularly those that discuss "syllogisms") are based on the much older work by Aristotle, but Aristotle expressly excluded empty sets from his system. Aristotle had a specific goal; he was trying to develop a "companion-logic" for science. He relegates fictions like fairy godmothers and mermaids and unicorns to the realms of poetry and literature... This is why he leaves no room for such nonexistent entities in his logic." (Groarke, "Aristotle: Logic", section 7. (Existential Assumptions), Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-log/ 4278). While this made sense for his purposes, it is less flexible than modern (classical) logic which does permit empty sets. If you wish to make claims that require a nonempty set, you must expressly include that requirement, e.g., by stating 𝑥𝜑. Examples of proofs that do this include barbari 2671, celaront 2673, and cesaro 2680.

For another "surprise" for new users of classical logic, see alimp-surprise 46343 and eximp-surprise 46347. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.)

¬ ∃𝑥 𝑥𝐴       𝑥𝐴 𝜑
 
Theoremempty-surprise2 46346 "Prove" that false is true when using a restricted "for all" over the empty set, to demonstrate that the expression is always true if the value ranges over the empty set.

Those inexperienced with formal notations of classical logic can be surprised with what restricted "for all" does over an empty set. We proved the general case in empty-surprise 46345. Here we prove an extreme example: we "prove" that false is true. Of course, we actually do no such thing (see notfal 1571); the problem is that restricted "for all" works in ways that might seem counterintuitive to the inexperienced when given an empty set. Solutions to this can include requiring that the set not be empty or by using the allsome quantifier df-alsc 46352. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.)

¬ ∃𝑥 𝑥𝐴       𝑥𝐴
 
Theoremeximp-surprise 46347 Show what implication inside "there exists" really expands to (using implication directly inside "there exists" is usually a mistake).

Those inexperienced with formal notations of classical logic may use expressions combining "there exists" with implication. That is usually a mistake, because as proven using imor 853, such an expression can be rewritten using not with or - and that is often not what the author intended. New users of formal notation who use "there exists" with an implication should consider if they meant "and" instead of "implies". A stark example is shown in eximp-surprise2 46348. See also alimp-surprise 46343 and empty-surprise 46345. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 17-Oct-2018.)

(∃𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ ∃𝑥𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremeximp-surprise2 46348 Show that "there exists" with an implication is always true if there exists a situation where the antecedent is false.

Those inexperienced with formal notations of classical logic may use expressions combining "there exists" with implication. This is usually a mistake, because that combination does not mean what an inexperienced person might think it means. For example, if there is some object that does not meet the precondition 𝜑, then the expression 𝑥(𝜑𝜓) as a whole is always true, no matter what 𝜓 is (𝜓 could even be false, ). New users of formal notation who use "there exists" with an implication should consider if they meant "and" instead of "implies". See eximp-surprise 46347, which shows what implication really expands to. See also empty-surprise 46345. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 18-Oct-2018.)

𝑥 ¬ 𝜑       𝑥(𝜑𝜓)
 
20.44.12  Allsome quantifier

These are definitions and proofs involving an experimental "allsome" quantifier (aka "all some").

In informal language, statements like "All Martians are green" imply that there is at least one Martian. But it's easy to mistranslate informal language into formal notations because similar statements like 𝑥𝜑𝜓 do not imply that 𝜑 is ever true, leading to vacuous truths. See alimp-surprise 46343 and empty-surprise 46345 as examples of the problem. Some systems include a mechanism to counter this, e.g., PVS allows types to be appended with "+" to declare that they are nonempty. This section presents a different solution to the same problem.

The "allsome" quantifier expressly includes the notion of both "all" and "there exists at least one" (aka some), and is defined to make it easier to more directly express both notions. The hope is that if a quantifier more directly expresses this concept, it will be used instead and reduce the risk of creating formal expressions that look okay but in fact are mistranslations. The term "allsome" was chosen because it's short, easy to say, and clearly hints at the two concepts it combines.

I do not expect this to be used much in Metamath, because in Metamath there's a general policy of avoiding the use of new definitions unless there are very strong reasons to do so. Instead, my goal is to rigorously define this quantifier and demonstrate a few basic properties of it.

The syntax allows two forms that look like they would be problematic, but they are fine. When applied to a top-level implication we allow ∀!𝑥(𝜑𝜓), and when restricted (applied to a class) we allow ∀!𝑥𝐴𝜑. The first symbol after the setvar variable must always be if it is the form applied to a class, and since cannot begin a wff, it is unambiguous. The looks like it would be a problem because 𝜑 or 𝜓 might include implications, but any implication arrow within any wff must be surrounded by parentheses, so only the implication arrow of ∀! can follow the wff. The implication syntax would work fine without the parentheses, but I added the parentheses because it makes things clearer inside larger complex expressions, and it's also more consistent with the rest of the syntax.

For more, see "The Allsome Quantifier" by David A. Wheeler at https://dwheeler.com/essays/allsome.html 46345 I hope that others will eventually agree that allsome is awesome.

 
Syntaxwalsi 46349 Extend wff definition to include "all some" applied to a top-level implication, which means 𝜓 is true whenever 𝜑 is true, and there is at least least one 𝑥 where 𝜑 is true. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.)
wff ∀!𝑥(𝜑𝜓)
 
Syntaxwalsc 46350 Extend wff definition to include "all some" applied to a class, which means 𝜑 is true for all 𝑥 in 𝐴, and there is at least one 𝑥 in 𝐴. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.)
wff ∀!𝑥𝐴𝜑
 
Definitiondf-alsi 46351 Define "all some" applied to a top-level implication, which means 𝜓 is true whenever 𝜑 is true and there is at least one 𝑥 where 𝜑 is true. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.)
(∀!𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ∧ ∃𝑥𝜑))
 
Definitiondf-alsc 46352 Define "all some" applied to a class, which means 𝜑 is true for all 𝑥 in 𝐴 and there is at least one 𝑥 in 𝐴. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.)
(∀!𝑥𝐴𝜑 ↔ (∀𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑥 𝑥𝐴))
 
Theoremalsconv 46353 There is an equivalence between the two "all some" forms. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 22-Oct-2018.)
(∀!𝑥(𝑥𝐴𝜑) ↔ ∀!𝑥𝐴𝜑)
 
Theoremalsi1d 46354 Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a top-level inference, you can extract the "for all" part. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.)
(𝜑 → ∀!𝑥(𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → ∀𝑥(𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremalsi2d 46355 Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a top-level inference, you can extract the "exists" part. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.)
(𝜑 → ∀!𝑥(𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓)
 
Theoremalsc1d 46356 Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a class, you can extract the "for all" part. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.)
(𝜑 → ∀!𝑥𝐴𝜓)       (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝐴 𝜓)
 
Theoremalsc2d 46357 Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a class, you can extract the "there exists" part. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.)
(𝜑 → ∀!𝑥𝐴𝜓)       (𝜑 → ∃𝑥 𝑥𝐴)
 
Theoremalscn0d 46358* Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a class, the class is not the empty set. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 23-Oct-2018.)
(𝜑 → ∀!𝑥𝐴𝜓)       (𝜑𝐴 ≠ ∅)
 
Theoremalsi-no-surprise 46359 Demonstrate that there is never a "surprise" when using the allsome quantifier, that is, it is never possible for the consequent to be both always true and always false. This uses the definition of df-alsi 46351; the proof itself builds on alimp-no-surprise 46344. For a contrast, see alimp-surprise 46343. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 27-Oct-2018.)
¬ (∀!𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ∧ ∀!𝑥(𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓))
 
20.44.13  Miscellaneous

Miscellaneous proofs.

 
Theorem5m4e1 46360 Prove that 5 - 4 = 1. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 31-Jan-2017.)
(5 − 4) = 1
 
Theorem2p2ne5 46361 Prove that 2 + 2 ≠ 5. In George Orwell's "1984", Part One, Chapter Seven, the protagonist Winston notes that, "In the end the Party would announce that two and two made five, and you would have to believe it." http://www.sparknotes.com/lit/1984/section4.rhtml. More generally, the phrase 2 + 2 = 5 has come to represent an obviously false dogma one may be required to believe. See the Wikipedia article for more about this: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/2_%2B_2_%3D_5. Unsurprisingly, we can easily prove that this claim is false. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 31-Jan-2017.)
(2 + 2) ≠ 5
 
Theoremresolution 46362 Resolution rule. This is the primary inference rule in some automated theorem provers such as prover9. The resolution rule can be traced back to Davis and Putnam (1960). (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 9-Feb-2017.)
(((𝜑𝜓) ∨ (¬ 𝜑𝜒)) → (𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremtestable 46363 In classical logic all wffs are testable, that is, it is always true that 𝜑 ∨ ¬ ¬ 𝜑). This is not necessarily true in intuitionistic logic. In intuitionistic logic, if this statement is true for some 𝜑, then 𝜑 is testable. The proof is trivial because it's simply a special case of the law of the excluded middle, which is true in classical logic but not necessarily true in intuitionisic logic. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 5-Dec-2018.)
𝜑 ∨ ¬ ¬ 𝜑)
 
20.44.14  Theorems about algebraic numbers
 
Theoremaacllem 46364* Lemma for other theorems about 𝔸. (Contributed by Brendan Leahy, 3-Jan-2020.) (Revised by Alexander van der Vekens and David A. Wheeler, 25-Apr-2020.)
(𝜑𝐴 ∈ ℂ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ0)    &   ((𝜑𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁)) → 𝑋 ∈ ℂ)    &   ((𝜑𝑘 ∈ (0...𝑁) ∧ 𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁)) → 𝐶 ∈ ℚ)    &   ((𝜑𝑘 ∈ (0...𝑁)) → (𝐴𝑘) = Σ𝑛 ∈ (1...𝑁)(𝐶 · 𝑋))       (𝜑𝐴 ∈ 𝔸)
 
20.45  Mathbox for Kunhao Zheng
 
20.45.1  Weighted AM-GM inequality
 
Theoremamgmwlem 46365 Weighted version of amgmlem 26019. (Contributed by Kunhao Zheng, 19-Jun-2021.)
𝑀 = (mulGrp‘ℂfld)    &   (𝜑𝐴 ∈ Fin)    &   (𝜑𝐴 ≠ ∅)    &   (𝜑𝐹:𝐴⟶ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝑊:𝐴⟶ℝ+)    &   (𝜑 → (ℂfld Σg 𝑊) = 1)       (𝜑 → (𝑀 Σg (𝐹f𝑐𝑊)) ≤ (ℂfld Σg (𝐹f · 𝑊)))
 
TheoremamgmlemALT 46366 Alternate proof of amgmlem 26019 using amgmwlem 46365. (Contributed by Kunhao Zheng, 20-Jun-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝑀 = (mulGrp‘ℂfld)    &   (𝜑𝐴 ∈ Fin)    &   (𝜑𝐴 ≠ ∅)    &   (𝜑𝐹:𝐴⟶ℝ+)       (𝜑 → ((𝑀 Σg 𝐹)↑𝑐(1 / (♯‘𝐴))) ≤ ((ℂfld Σg 𝐹) / (♯‘𝐴)))
 
Theoremamgmw2d 46367 Weighted arithmetic-geometric mean inequality for 𝑛 = 2 (compare amgm2d 41671). (Contributed by Kunhao Zheng, 20-Jun-2021.)
(𝜑𝐴 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝑃 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝐵 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝑄 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑 → (𝑃 + 𝑄) = 1)       (𝜑 → ((𝐴𝑐𝑃) · (𝐵𝑐𝑄)) ≤ ((𝐴 · 𝑃) + (𝐵 · 𝑄)))
 
Theoremyoung2d 46368 Young's inequality for 𝑛 = 2, a direct application of amgmw2d 46367. (Contributed by Kunhao Zheng, 6-Jul-2021.)
(𝜑𝐴 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝑃 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝐵 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝑄 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑 → ((1 / 𝑃) + (1 / 𝑄)) = 1)       (𝜑 → (𝐴 · 𝐵) ≤ (((𝐴𝑐𝑃) / 𝑃) + ((𝐵𝑐𝑄) / 𝑄)))
    < Previous  Wrap >

Page List
Jump to page: Contents  1 1-100 2 101-200 3 201-300 4 301-400 5 401-500 6 501-600 7 601-700 8 701-800 9 801-900 10 901-1000 11 1001-1100 12 1101-1200 13 1201-1300 14 1301-1400 15 1401-1500 16 1501-1600 17 1601-1700 18 1701-1800 19 1801-1900 20 1901-2000 21 2001-2100 22 2101-2200 23 2201-2300 24 2301-2400 25 2401-2500 26 2501-2600 27 2601-2700 28 2701-2800 29 2801-2900 30 2901-3000 31 3001-3100 32 3101-3200 33 3201-3300 34 3301-3400 35 3401-3500 36 3501-3600 37 3601-3700 38 3701-3800 39 3801-3900 40 3901-4000 41 4001-4100 42 4101-4200 43 4201-4300 44 4301-4400 45 4401-4500 46 4501-4600 47 4601-4700 48 4701-4800 49 4801-4900 50 4901-5000 51 5001-5100 52 5101-5200 53 5201-5300 54 5301-5400 55 5401-5500 56 5501-5600 57 5601-5700 58 5701-5800 59 5801-5900 60 5901-6000 61 6001-6100 62 6101-6200 63 6201-6300 64 6301-6400 65 6401-6500 66 6501-6600 67 6601-6700 68 6701-6800 69 6801-6900 70 6901-7000 71 7001-7100 72 7101-7200 73 7201-7300 74 7301-7400 75 7401-7500 76 7501-7600 77 7601-7700 78 7701-7800 79 7801-7900 80 7901-8000 81 8001-8100 82 8101-8200 83 8201-8300 84 8301-8400 85 8401-8500 86 8501-8600 87 8601-8700 88 8701-8800 89 8801-8900 90 8901-9000 91 9001-9100 92 9101-9200 93 9201-9300 94 9301-9400 95 9401-9500 96 9501-9600 97 9601-9700 98 9701-9800 99 9801-9900 100 9901-10000 101 10001-10100 102 10101-10200 103 10201-10300 104 10301-10400 105 10401-10500 106 10501-10600 107 10601-10700 108 10701-10800 109 10801-10900 110 10901-11000 111 11001-11100 112 11101-11200 113 11201-11300 114 11301-11400 115 11401-11500 116 11501-11600 117 11601-11700 118 11701-11800 119 11801-11900 120 11901-12000 121 12001-12100 122 12101-12200 123 12201-12300 124 12301-12400 125 12401-12500 126 12501-12600 127 12601-12700 128 12701-12800 129 12801-12900 130 12901-13000 131 13001-13100 132 13101-13200 133 13201-13300 134 13301-13400 135 13401-13500 136 13501-13600 137 13601-13700 138 13701-13800 139 13801-13900 140 13901-14000 141 14001-14100 142 14101-14200 143 14201-14300 144 14301-14400 145 14401-14500 146 14501-14600 147 14601-14700 148 14701-14800 149 14801-14900 150 14901-15000 151 15001-15100 152 15101-15200 153 15201-15300 154 15301-15400 155 15401-15500 156 15501-15600 157 15601-15700 158 15701-15800 159 15801-15900 160 15901-16000 161 16001-16100 162 16101-16200 163 16201-16300 164 16301-16400 165 16401-16500 166 16501-16600 167 16601-16700 168 16701-16800 169 16801-16900 170 16901-17000 171 17001-17100 172 17101-17200 173 17201-17300 174 17301-17400 175 17401-17500 176 17501-17600 177 17601-17700 178 17701-17800 179 17801-17900 180 17901-18000 181 18001-18100 182 18101-18200 183 18201-18300 184 18301-18400 185 18401-18500 186 18501-18600 187 18601-18700 188 18701-18800 189 18801-18900 190 18901-19000 191 19001-19100 192 19101-19200 193 19201-19300 194 19301-19400 195 19401-19500 196 19501-19600 197 19601-19700 198 19701-19800 199 19801-19900 200 19901-20000 201 20001-20100 202 20101-20200 203 20201-20300 204 20301-20400 205 20401-20500 206 20501-20600 207 20601-20700 208 20701-20800 209 20801-20900 210 20901-21000 211 21001-21100 212 21101-21200 213 21201-21300 214 21301-21400 215 21401-21500 216 21501-21600 217 21601-21700 218 21701-21800 219 21801-21900 220 21901-22000 221 22001-22100 222 22101-22200 223 22201-22300 224 22301-22400 225 22401-22500 226 22501-22600 227 22601-22700 228 22701-22800 229 22801-22900 230 22901-23000 231 23001-23100 232 23101-23200 233 23201-23300 234 23301-23400 235 23401-23500 236 23501-23600 237 23601-23700 238 23701-23800 239 23801-23900 240 23901-24000 241 24001-24100 242 24101-24200 243 24201-24300 244 24301-24400 245 24401-24500 246 24501-24600 247 24601-24700 248 24701-24800 249 24801-24900 250 24901-25000 251 25001-25100 252 25101-25200 253 25201-25300 254 25301-25400 255 25401-25500 256 25501-25600 257 25601-25700 258 25701-25800 259 25801-25900 260 25901-26000 261 26001-26100 262 26101-26200 263 26201-26300 264 26301-26400 265 26401-26500 266 26501-26600 267 26601-26700 268 26701-26800 269 26801-26900 270 26901-27000 271 27001-27100 272 27101-27200 273 27201-27300 274 27301-27400 275 27401-27500 276 27501-27600 277 27601-27700 278 27701-27800 279 27801-27900 280 27901-28000 281 28001-28100 282 28101-28200 283 28201-28300 284 28301-28400 285 28401-28500 286 28501-28600 287 28601-28700 288 28701-28800 289 28801-28900 290 28901-29000 291 29001-29100 292 29101-29200 293 29201-29300 294 29301-29400 295 29401-29500 296 29501-29600 297 29601-29700 298 29701-29800 299 29801-29900 300 29901-30000 301 30001-30100 302 30101-30200 303 30201-30300 304 30301-30400 305 30401-30500 306 30501-30600 307 30601-30700 308 30701-30800 309 30801-30900 310 30901-31000 311 31001-31100 312 31101-31200 313 31201-31300 314 31301-31400 315 31401-31500 316 31501-31600 317 31601-31700 318 31701-31800 319 31801-31900 320 31901-32000 321 32001-32100 322 32101-32200 323 32201-32300 324 32301-32400 325 32401-32500 326 32501-32600 327 32601-32700 328 32701-32800 329 32801-32900 330 32901-33000 331 33001-33100 332 33101-33200 333 33201-33300 334 33301-33400 335 33401-33500 336 33501-33600 337 33601-33700 338 33701-33800 339 33801-33900 340 33901-34000 341 34001-34100 342 34101-34200 343 34201-34300 344 34301-34400 345 34401-34500 346 34501-34600 347 34601-34700 348 34701-34800 349 34801-34900 350 34901-35000 351 35001-35100 352 35101-35200 353 35201-35300 354 35301-35400 355 35401-35500 356 35501-35600 357 35601-35700 358 35701-35800 359 35801-35900 360 35901-36000 361 36001-36100 362 36101-36200 363 36201-36300 364 36301-36400 365 36401-36500 366 36501-36600 367 36601-36700 368 36701-36800 369 36801-36900 370 36901-37000 371 37001-37100 372 37101-37200 373 37201-37300 374 37301-37400 375 37401-37500 376 37501-37600 377 37601-37700 378 37701-37800 379 37801-37900 380 37901-38000 381 38001-38100 382 38101-38200 383 38201-38300 384 38301-38400 385 38401-38500 386 38501-38600 387 38601-38700 388 38701-38800 389 38801-38900 390 38901-39000 391 39001-39100 392 39101-39200 393 39201-39300 394 39301-39400 395 39401-39500 396 39501-39600 397 39601-39700 398 39701-39800 399 39801-39900 400 39901-40000 401 40001-40100 402 40101-40200 403 40201-40300 404 40301-40400 405 40401-40500 406 40501-40600 407 40601-40700 408 40701-40800 409 40801-40900 410 40901-41000 411 41001-41100 412 41101-41200 413 41201-41300 414 41301-41400 415 41401-41500 416 41501-41600 417 41601-41700 418 41701-41800 419 41801-41900 420 41901-42000 421 42001-42100 422 42101-42200 423 42201-42300 424 42301-42400 425 42401-42500 426 42501-42600 427 42601-42700 428 42701-42800 429 42801-42900 430 42901-43000 431 43001-43100 432 43101-43200 433 43201-43300 434 43301-43400 435 43401-43500 436 43501-43600 437 43601-43700 438 43701-43800 439 43801-43900 440 43901-44000 441 44001-44100 442 44101-44200 443 44201-44300 444 44301-44400 445 44401-44500 446 44501-44600 447 44601-44700 448 44701-44800 449 44801-44900 450 44901-45000 451 45001-45100 452 45101-45200 453 45201-45300 454 45301-45400 455 45401-45500 456 45501-45600 457 45601-45700 458 45701-45800 459 45801-45900 460 45901-46000 461 46001-46100 462 46101-46200 463 46201-46300 464 46301-46368
  Copyright terms: Public domain < Previous  Wrap >