Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 98 of 464) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29156) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29157-30679) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30680-46368) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | ssnum 9701 | A subset of a numerable set is numerable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | onssnum 9702 | All subsets of the ordinals are numerable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ On) → 𝐴 ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | indcardi 9703* | Indirect strong induction on the cardinality of a finite or numerable set. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ dom card) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑅 ≼ 𝑇 ∧ ∀𝑦(𝑆 ≺ 𝑅 → 𝜒)) → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝑅 = 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝑅 = 𝑇) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | acnrcl 9704 | Reverse closure for the choice set predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴 → 𝐴 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | acneq 9705 | Equality theorem for the choice set function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐶 → AC 𝐴 = AC 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | isacn 9706* | The property of being a choice set of length 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑓 ∈ ((𝒫 𝑋 ∖ {∅}) ↑m 𝐴)∃𝑔∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑔‘𝑥) ∈ (𝑓‘𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | acni 9707* | The property of being a choice set of length 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶(𝒫 𝑋 ∖ {∅})) → ∃𝑔∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑔‘𝑥) ∈ (𝐹‘𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | acni2 9708* | The property of being a choice set of length 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐵 ⊆ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅)) → ∃𝑔(𝑔:𝐴⟶𝑋 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑔‘𝑥) ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | acni3 9709* | The property of being a choice set of length 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑦 = (𝑔‘𝑥) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 𝜑) → ∃𝑔(𝑔:𝐴⟶𝑋 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | acnlem 9710* | Construct a mapping satisfying the consequent of isacn 9706. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ (𝑓‘𝑥)) → ∃𝑔∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑔‘𝑥) ∈ (𝑓‘𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | numacn 9711 | A well-orderable set has choice sequences of every length. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝑋 ∈ dom card → 𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | finacn 9712 | Every set has finite choice sequences. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Fin → AC 𝐴 = V) | ||
Theorem | acndom 9713 | A set with long choice sequences also has shorter choice sequences, where "shorter" here means the new index set is dominated by the old index set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 → (𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐵 → 𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | acnnum 9714 | A set 𝑋 which has choice sequences on it of length 𝒫 𝑋 is well-orderable (and hence has choice sequences of every length). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ AC 𝒫 𝑋 ↔ 𝑋 ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | acnen 9715 | The class of choice sets of length 𝐴 is a cardinal invariant. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 → AC 𝐴 = AC 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | acndom2 9716 | A set smaller than one with choice sequences of length 𝐴 also has choice sequences of length 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ≼ 𝑌 → (𝑌 ∈ AC 𝐴 → 𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | acnen2 9717 | The class of sets with choice sequences of length 𝐴 is a cardinal invariant. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ≈ 𝑌 → (𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴 ↔ 𝑌 ∈ AC 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | fodomacn 9718 | A version of fodom 10185 that doesn't require the Axiom of Choice ax-ac 10121. If 𝐴 has choice sequences of length 𝐵, then any surjection from 𝐴 to 𝐵 can be inverted to an injection the other way. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ AC 𝐵 → (𝐹:𝐴–onto→𝐵 → 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | fodomnum 9719 | A version of fodom 10185 that doesn't require the Axiom of Choice ax-ac 10121. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ dom card → (𝐹:𝐴–onto→𝐵 → 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | fonum 9720 | A surjection maps numerable sets to numerable sets. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–onto→𝐵) → 𝐵 ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | numwdom 9721 | A surjection maps numerable sets to numerable sets. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ≼* 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | fodomfi2 9722 | Onto functions define dominance when a finite number of choices need to be made. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 28-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–onto→𝐵) → 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | wdomfil 9723 | Weak dominance agrees with normal for finite left sets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 28-Feb-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 5-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ Fin → (𝑋 ≼* 𝑌 ↔ 𝑋 ≼ 𝑌)) | ||
Theorem | infpwfien 9724 | Any infinite well-orderable set is equinumerous to its set of finite subsets. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴) → (𝒫 𝐴 ∩ Fin) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | inffien 9725 | The set of finite intersections of an infinite well-orderable set is equinumerous to the set itself. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴) → (fi‘𝐴) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | wdomnumr 9726 | Weak dominance agrees with normal for numerable right sets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 28-Feb-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 5-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ dom card → (𝐴 ≼* 𝐵 ↔ 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | alephfnon 9727 | The aleph function is a function on the class of ordinal numbers. (Contributed by NM, 21-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 13-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ ℵ Fn On | ||
Theorem | aleph0 9728 | The first infinite cardinal number, discovered by Georg Cantor in 1873, has the same size as the set of natural numbers ω (and under our particular definition is also equal to it). In the literature, the argument of the aleph function is often written as a subscript, and the first aleph is written ℵ0. Exercise 3 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 91. Also Definition 12(i) of [Suppes] p. 228. From Moshé Machover, Set Theory, Logic, and Their Limitations, p. 95: "Aleph ... the first letter in the Hebrew alphabet ... is also the first letter of the Hebrew word ... (einsoph, meaning infinity), which is a cabbalistic appellation of the deity. The notation is due to Cantor, who was deeply interested in mysticism." (Contributed by NM, 21-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 13-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ (ℵ‘∅) = ω | ||
Theorem | alephlim 9729* | Value of the aleph function at a limit ordinal. Definition 12(iii) of [Suppes] p. 91. (Contributed by NM, 21-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 13-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ Lim 𝐴) → (ℵ‘𝐴) = ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (ℵ‘𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | alephsuc 9730 | Value of the aleph function at a successor ordinal. Definition 12(ii) of [Suppes] p. 91. Here we express the successor aleph in terms of the Hartogs function df-har 9221, which gives the smallest ordinal that strictly dominates its argument (or the supremum of all ordinals that are dominated by the argument). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 13-Sep-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (ℵ‘suc 𝐴) = (har‘(ℵ‘𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | alephon 9731 | An aleph is an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 10-Nov-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 13-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ (ℵ‘𝐴) ∈ On | ||
Theorem | alephcard 9732 | Every aleph is a cardinal number. Theorem 65 of [Suppes] p. 229. (Contributed by NM, 25-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (card‘(ℵ‘𝐴)) = (ℵ‘𝐴) | ||
Theorem | alephnbtwn 9733 | No cardinal can be sandwiched between an aleph and its successor aleph. Theorem 67 of [Suppes] p. 229. (Contributed by NM, 10-Nov-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((card‘𝐵) = 𝐵 → ¬ ((ℵ‘𝐴) ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (ℵ‘suc 𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | alephnbtwn2 9734 | No set has equinumerosity between an aleph and its successor aleph. (Contributed by NM, 3-Nov-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ¬ ((ℵ‘𝐴) ≺ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ≺ (ℵ‘suc 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | alephordilem1 9735 | Lemma for alephordi 9736. (Contributed by NM, 23-Oct-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (ℵ‘𝐴) ≺ (ℵ‘suc 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | alephordi 9736 | Strict ordering property of the aleph function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ On → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (ℵ‘𝐴) ≺ (ℵ‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | alephord 9737 | Ordering property of the aleph function. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ (ℵ‘𝐴) ≺ (ℵ‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | alephord2 9738 | Ordering property of the aleph function. Theorem 8A(a) of [Enderton] p. 213 and its converse. (Contributed by NM, 3-Nov-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ (ℵ‘𝐴) ∈ (ℵ‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | alephord2i 9739 | Ordering property of the aleph function. Theorem 66 of [Suppes] p. 229. (Contributed by NM, 25-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ On → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (ℵ‘𝐴) ∈ (ℵ‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | alephord3 9740 | Ordering property of the aleph function. (Contributed by NM, 11-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ (ℵ‘𝐴) ⊆ (ℵ‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | alephsucdom 9741 | A set dominated by an aleph is strictly dominated by its successor aleph and vice-versa. (Contributed by NM, 3-Nov-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ On → (𝐴 ≼ (ℵ‘𝐵) ↔ 𝐴 ≺ (ℵ‘suc 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | alephsuc2 9742* | An alternate representation of a successor aleph. The aleph function is the function obtained from the hartogs 9208 function by transfinite recursion, starting from ω. Using this theorem we could define the aleph function with {𝑧 ∈ On ∣ 𝑧 ≼ 𝑥} in place of ∩ {𝑧 ∈ On ∣ 𝑥 ≺ 𝑧} in df-aleph 9604. (Contributed by NM, 3-Nov-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (ℵ‘suc 𝐴) = {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ 𝑥 ≼ (ℵ‘𝐴)}) | ||
Theorem | alephdom 9743 | Relationship between inclusion of ordinal numbers and dominance of infinite initial ordinals. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 23-Oct-2009.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ (ℵ‘𝐴) ≼ (ℵ‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | alephgeom 9744 | Every aleph is greater than or equal to the set of natural numbers. (Contributed by NM, 11-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On ↔ ω ⊆ (ℵ‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | alephislim 9745 | Every aleph is a limit ordinal. (Contributed by NM, 11-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On ↔ Lim (ℵ‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | aleph11 9746 | The aleph function is one-to-one. (Contributed by NM, 3-Aug-2004.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → ((ℵ‘𝐴) = (ℵ‘𝐵) ↔ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | alephf1 9747 | The aleph function is a one-to-one mapping from the ordinals to the infinite cardinals. See also alephf1ALT 9765. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ℵ:On–1-1→On | ||
Theorem | alephsdom 9748 | If an ordinal is smaller than an initial ordinal, it is strictly dominated by it. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 24-Oct-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ∈ (ℵ‘𝐵) ↔ 𝐴 ≺ (ℵ‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | alephdom2 9749 | A dominated initial ordinal is included. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 24-Oct-2009.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → ((ℵ‘𝐴) ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ (ℵ‘𝐴) ≼ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | alephle 9750 | The argument of the aleph function is less than or equal to its value. Exercise 2 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 91. (Later, in alephfp2 9771, we will that equality can sometimes hold.) (Contributed by NM, 9-Nov-2003.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 22-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → 𝐴 ⊆ (ℵ‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | cardaleph 9751* | Given any transfinite cardinal number 𝐴, there is exactly one aleph that is equal to it. Here we compute that aleph explicitly. (Contributed by NM, 9-Nov-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ((ω ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ (card‘𝐴) = 𝐴) → 𝐴 = (ℵ‘∩ {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ 𝐴 ⊆ (ℵ‘𝑥)})) | ||
Theorem | cardalephex 9752* | Every transfinite cardinal is an aleph and vice-versa. Theorem 8A(b) of [Enderton] p. 213 and its converse. (Contributed by NM, 5-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ (ω ⊆ 𝐴 → ((card‘𝐴) = 𝐴 ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ On 𝐴 = (ℵ‘𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | infenaleph 9753* | An infinite numerable set is equinumerous to an infinite initial ordinal. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 23-Oct-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴) → ∃𝑥 ∈ ran ℵ𝑥 ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | isinfcard 9754 | Two ways to express the property of being a transfinite cardinal. (Contributed by NM, 9-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ((ω ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ (card‘𝐴) = 𝐴) ↔ 𝐴 ∈ ran ℵ) | ||
Theorem | iscard3 9755 | Two ways to express the property of being a cardinal number. (Contributed by NM, 9-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ((card‘𝐴) = 𝐴 ↔ 𝐴 ∈ (ω ∪ ran ℵ)) | ||
Theorem | cardnum 9756 | Two ways to express the class of all cardinal numbers, which consists of the finite ordinals in ω plus the transfinite alephs. (Contributed by NM, 10-Sep-2004.) |
⊢ {𝑥 ∣ (card‘𝑥) = 𝑥} = (ω ∪ ran ℵ) | ||
Theorem | alephinit 9757* | An infinite initial ordinal is characterized by the property of being initial - that is, it is a subset of any dominating ordinal. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 29-Oct-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ ω ⊆ 𝐴) → (𝐴 ∈ ran ℵ ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ On (𝐴 ≼ 𝑥 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | carduniima 9758 | The union of the image of a mapping to cardinals is a cardinal. Proposition 11.16 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 104. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (𝐹:𝐴⟶(ω ∪ ran ℵ) → ∪ (𝐹 “ 𝐴) ∈ (ω ∪ ran ℵ))) | ||
Theorem | cardinfima 9759* | If a mapping to cardinals has an infinite value, then the union of its image is an infinite cardinal. Corollary 11.17 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 104. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → ((𝐹:𝐴⟶(ω ∪ ran ℵ) ∧ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐹‘𝑥) ∈ ran ℵ) → ∪ (𝐹 “ 𝐴) ∈ ran ℵ)) | ||
Theorem | alephiso 9760 | Aleph is an order isomorphism of the class of ordinal numbers onto the class of infinite cardinals. Definition 10.27 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 3-Aug-2004.) |
⊢ ℵ Isom E , E (On, {𝑥 ∣ (ω ⊆ 𝑥 ∧ (card‘𝑥) = 𝑥)}) | ||
Theorem | alephprc 9761 | The class of all transfinite cardinal numbers (the range of the aleph function) is a proper class. Proposition 10.26 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 11-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ¬ ran ℵ ∈ V | ||
Theorem | alephsson 9762 | The class of transfinite cardinals (the range of the aleph function) is a subclass of the class of ordinal numbers. (Contributed by NM, 11-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ran ℵ ⊆ On | ||
Theorem | unialeph 9763 | The union of the class of transfinite cardinals (the range of the aleph function) is the class of ordinal numbers. (Contributed by NM, 11-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ∪ ran ℵ = On | ||
Theorem | alephsmo 9764 | The aleph function is strictly monotone. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ Smo ℵ | ||
Theorem | alephf1ALT 9765 | Alternate proof of alephf1 9747. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Mar-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ℵ:On–1-1→On | ||
Theorem | alephfplem1 9766 | Lemma for alephfp 9770. (Contributed by NM, 6-Nov-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐻 = (rec(ℵ, ω) ↾ ω) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐻‘∅) ∈ ran ℵ | ||
Theorem | alephfplem2 9767* | Lemma for alephfp 9770. (Contributed by NM, 6-Nov-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐻 = (rec(ℵ, ω) ↾ ω) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑤 ∈ ω → (𝐻‘suc 𝑤) = (ℵ‘(𝐻‘𝑤))) | ||
Theorem | alephfplem3 9768* | Lemma for alephfp 9770. (Contributed by NM, 6-Nov-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐻 = (rec(ℵ, ω) ↾ ω) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑣 ∈ ω → (𝐻‘𝑣) ∈ ran ℵ) | ||
Theorem | alephfplem4 9769 | Lemma for alephfp 9770. (Contributed by NM, 5-Nov-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐻 = (rec(ℵ, ω) ↾ ω) ⇒ ⊢ ∪ (𝐻 “ ω) ∈ ran ℵ | ||
Theorem | alephfp 9770 | The aleph function has a fixed point. Similar to Proposition 11.18 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 104, except that we construct an actual example of a fixed point rather than just showing its existence. See alephfp2 9771 for an abbreviated version just showing existence. (Contributed by NM, 6-Nov-2004.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐻 = (rec(ℵ, ω) ↾ ω) ⇒ ⊢ (ℵ‘∪ (𝐻 “ ω)) = ∪ (𝐻 “ ω) | ||
Theorem | alephfp2 9771 | The aleph function has at least one fixed point. Proposition 11.18 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 104. See alephfp 9770 for an actual example of a fixed point. Compare the inequality alephle 9750 that holds in general. Note that if 𝑥 is a fixed point, then ℵ‘ℵ‘ℵ‘... ℵ‘𝑥 = 𝑥. (Contributed by NM, 6-Nov-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥 ∈ On (ℵ‘𝑥) = 𝑥 | ||
Theorem | alephval3 9772* | An alternate way to express the value of the aleph function: it is the least infinite cardinal different from all values at smaller arguments. Definition of aleph in [Enderton] p. 212 and definition of aleph in [BellMachover] p. 490 . (Contributed by NM, 16-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (ℵ‘𝐴) = ∩ {𝑥 ∣ ((card‘𝑥) = 𝑥 ∧ ω ⊆ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ¬ 𝑥 = (ℵ‘𝑦))}) | ||
Theorem | alephsucpw2 9773 | The power set of an aleph is not strictly dominated by the successor aleph. (The Generalized Continuum Hypothesis says they are equinumerous, see gch3 10338 or gchaleph2 10334.) The transposed form alephsucpw 10232 cannot be proven without the AC, and is in fact equivalent to it. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝒫 (ℵ‘𝐴) ≺ (ℵ‘suc 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | mappwen 9774 | Power rule for cardinal arithmetic. Theorem 11.21 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 106. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Mar-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 27-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝐵 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐵) ∧ (2o ≼ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 ≼ 𝒫 𝐵)) → (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ≈ 𝒫 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | finnisoeu 9775* | A finite totally ordered set has a unique order isomorphism to a finite ordinal. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 16-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ Fin) → ∃!𝑓 𝑓 Isom E , 𝑅 ((card‘𝐴), 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | iunfictbso 9776 | Countability of a countable union of finite sets with a strict (not globally well) order fulfilling the choice role. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 16-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ ω ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ Fin ∧ 𝐵 Or ∪ 𝐴) → ∪ 𝐴 ≼ ω) | ||
Syntax | wac 9777 | Wff for an abbreviation of the axiom of choice. |
wff CHOICE | ||
Definition | df-ac 9778* |
The expression CHOICE will be used as a
readable shorthand for any
form of the axiom of choice; all concrete forms are long, cryptic, have
dummy variables, or all three, making it useful to have a short name.
Similar to the Axiom of Choice (first form) of [Enderton] p. 49.
There is a slight problem with taking the exact form of ax-ac 10121 as our definition, because the equivalence to more standard forms (dfac2 9793) requires the Axiom of Regularity, which we often try to avoid. Thus, we take the first of the "textbook forms" as the definition and derive the form of ax-ac 10121 itself as dfac0 9795. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑓(𝑓 ⊆ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑓 Fn dom 𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | aceq1 9779* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice ax-ac 10121. The proof uses neither AC nor the Axiom of Regularity. The right-hand side expresses our AC with the fewest number of different variables. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃!𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑢 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑢) ↔ ∃𝑦∀𝑧∀𝑤((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) → ∃𝑥∀𝑧(∃𝑥((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦)) ↔ 𝑧 = 𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | aceq0 9780* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice. The proof uses neither AC nor the Axiom of Regularity. The right-hand side is our original ax-ac 10121. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃!𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑢 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑢) ↔ ∃𝑦∀𝑧∀𝑤((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) → ∃𝑣∀𝑢(∃𝑡((𝑢 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑡) ∧ (𝑢 ∈ 𝑡 ∧ 𝑡 ∈ 𝑦)) ↔ 𝑢 = 𝑣))) | ||
Theorem | aceq2 9781* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice. The proof uses neither AC nor the Axiom of Regularity. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃!𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑢 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑢) ↔ ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → ∃!𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑣 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑣 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑣))) | ||
Theorem | aceq3lem 9782* | Lemma for dfac3 9783. (Contributed by NM, 2-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑤 ∈ dom 𝑦 ↦ (𝑓‘{𝑢 ∣ 𝑤𝑦𝑢})) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥∃𝑓∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → (𝑓‘𝑧) ∈ 𝑧) → ∃𝑓(𝑓 ⊆ 𝑦 ∧ 𝑓 Fn dom 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | dfac3 9783* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice. The left-hand side is defined as the Axiom of Choice (first form) of [Enderton] p. 49. The right-hand side is the Axiom of Choice of [TakeutiZaring] p. 83. The proof does not depend on AC. (Contributed by NM, 24-Mar-2004.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑓∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → (𝑓‘𝑧) ∈ 𝑧)) | ||
Theorem | dfac4 9784* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice. The right-hand side is Axiom AC of [BellMachover] p. 488. The proof does not depend on AC. (Contributed by NM, 24-Mar-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑓(𝑓 Fn 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → (𝑓‘𝑧) ∈ 𝑧))) | ||
Theorem | dfac5lem1 9785* | Lemma for dfac5 9790. (Contributed by NM, 12-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (({𝑤} × 𝑤) ∩ 𝑦) ↔ ∃!𝑔(𝑔 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 〈𝑤, 𝑔〉 ∈ 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | dfac5lem2 9786* | Lemma for dfac5 9790. (Contributed by NM, 12-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ (𝑢 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∃𝑡 ∈ ℎ 𝑢 = ({𝑡} × 𝑡))} ⇒ ⊢ (〈𝑤, 𝑔〉 ∈ ∪ 𝐴 ↔ (𝑤 ∈ ℎ ∧ 𝑔 ∈ 𝑤)) | ||
Theorem | dfac5lem3 9787* | Lemma for dfac5 9790. (Contributed by NM, 12-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ (𝑢 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∃𝑡 ∈ ℎ 𝑢 = ({𝑡} × 𝑡))} ⇒ ⊢ (({𝑤} × 𝑤) ∈ 𝐴 ↔ (𝑤 ≠ ∅ ∧ 𝑤 ∈ ℎ)) | ||
Theorem | dfac5lem4 9788* | Lemma for dfac5 9790. (Contributed by NM, 11-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ (𝑢 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∃𝑡 ∈ ℎ 𝑢 = ({𝑡} × 𝑡))} & ⊢ 𝐵 = (∪ 𝐴 ∩ 𝑦) & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥((∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 𝑧 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 → (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤) = ∅)) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | dfac5lem5 9789* | Lemma for dfac5 9790. (Contributed by NM, 12-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ (𝑢 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∃𝑡 ∈ ℎ 𝑢 = ({𝑡} × 𝑡))} & ⊢ 𝐵 = (∪ 𝐴 ∩ 𝑦) & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥((∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 𝑧 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 → (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤) = ∅)) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑓∀𝑤 ∈ ℎ (𝑤 ≠ ∅ → (𝑓‘𝑤) ∈ 𝑤)) | ||
Theorem | dfac5 9790* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice. The right-hand side is Theorem 6M(4) of [Enderton] p. 151 and asserts that given a family of mutually disjoint nonempty sets, a set exists containing exactly one member from each set in the family. The proof does not depend on AC. (Contributed by NM, 11-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥((∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 𝑧 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 → (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤) = ∅)) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | dfac2a 9791* | Our Axiom of Choice (in the form of ac3 10124) implies the Axiom of Choice (first form) of [Enderton] p. 49. The proof uses neither AC nor the Axiom of Regularity. See dfac2b 9792 for the converse (which does use the Axiom of Regularity). (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → ∃!𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑣 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑣 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑣)) → CHOICE) | ||
Theorem | dfac2b 9792* | Axiom of Choice (first form) of [Enderton] p. 49 implies our Axiom of Choice (in the form of ac3 10124). The proof does not make use of AC. Note that the Axiom of Regularity is used by the proof. Specifically, elneq 9262 and preleq 9279 that are referenced in the proof each make use of Regularity for their derivations. (The reverse implication can be derived without using Regularity; see dfac2a 9791.) (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) (Revised by AV, 16-Jun-2022.) |
⊢ (CHOICE → ∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → ∃!𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑣 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑣 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑣))) | ||
Theorem | dfac2 9793* | Axiom of Choice (first form) of [Enderton] p. 49 corresponds to our Axiom of Choice (in the form of ac3 10124). The proof does not make use of AC, but the Axiom of Regularity is used (by applying dfac2b 9792). (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) (Revised by AV, 16-Jun-2022.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → ∃!𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑣 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑣 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑣))) | ||
Theorem | dfac7 9794* | Equivalence of the Axiom of Choice (first form) of [Enderton] p. 49 and our Axiom of Choice (in the form of ac2 10123). The proof does not depend on AC but does depend on the Axiom of Regularity. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃!𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑢 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑢)) | ||
Theorem | dfac0 9795* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice. The proof uses the Axiom of Regularity. The right-hand side is our original ax-ac 10121. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧∀𝑤((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) → ∃𝑣∀𝑢(∃𝑡((𝑢 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑡) ∧ (𝑢 ∈ 𝑡 ∧ 𝑡 ∈ 𝑦)) ↔ 𝑢 = 𝑣))) | ||
Theorem | dfac1 9796* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice ax-ac 10121. The proof uses the Axiom of Regularity. The right-hand side expresses our AC with the fewest number of different variables. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧∀𝑤((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) → ∃𝑥∀𝑧(∃𝑥((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦)) ↔ 𝑧 = 𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | dfac8 9797* | A proof of the equivalency of the well-ordering theorem weth 10157 and the axiom of choice ac7 10135. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑟 𝑟 We 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | dfac9 9798* | Equivalence of the axiom of choice with a statement related to ac9 10145; definition AC3 of [Schechter] p. 139. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑓((Fun 𝑓 ∧ ∅ ∉ ran 𝑓) → X𝑥 ∈ dom 𝑓(𝑓‘𝑥) ≠ ∅)) | ||
Theorem | dfac10 9799 | Axiom of Choice equivalent: the cardinality function measures every set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ dom card = V) | ||
Theorem | dfac10c 9800* | Axiom of Choice equivalent: every set is equinumerous to an ordinal. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑦 ∈ On 𝑦 ≈ 𝑥) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |