![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 100 of 474) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-29923) |
![]() (29924-31446) |
![]() (31447-47372) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | oncardid 9901 | Any ordinal number is equinumerous to its cardinal number. Unlike cardid 10492, this theorem does not require the Axiom of Choice. (Contributed by NM, 26-Jul-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (card‘𝐴) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | cardonle 9902 | The cardinal of an ordinal number is less than or equal to the ordinal number. Proposition 10.6(3) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 85. (Contributed by NM, 22-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (card‘𝐴) ⊆ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | card0 9903 | The cardinality of the empty set is the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 25-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ (card‘∅) = ∅ | ||
Theorem | cardidm 9904 | The cardinality function is idempotent. Proposition 10.11 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 85. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (card‘(card‘𝐴)) = (card‘𝐴) | ||
Theorem | oncard 9905* | A set is a cardinal number iff it equals its own cardinal number. Proposition 10.9 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 85. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥 𝐴 = (card‘𝑥) ↔ 𝐴 = (card‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ficardom 9906 | The cardinal number of a finite set is a finite ordinal. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 11-Apr-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Fin → (card‘𝐴) ∈ ω) | ||
Theorem | ficardid 9907 | A finite set is equinumerous to its cardinal number. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 21-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Fin → (card‘𝐴) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | cardnn 9908 | The cardinality of a natural number is the number. Corollary 10.23 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (card‘𝐴) = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | cardnueq0 9909 | The empty set is the only numerable set with cardinality zero. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ dom card → ((card‘𝐴) = ∅ ↔ 𝐴 = ∅)) | ||
Theorem | cardne 9910 | No member of a cardinal number of a set is equinumerous to the set. Proposition 10.6(2) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 85. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (card‘𝐵) → ¬ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | carden2a 9911 | If two sets have equal nonzero cardinalities, then they are equinumerous. This assertion and carden2b 9912 are meant to replace carden 10496 in ZF without AC. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (((card‘𝐴) = (card‘𝐵) ∧ (card‘𝐴) ≠ ∅) → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | carden2b 9912 | If two sets are equinumerous, then they have equal cardinalities. (This assertion and carden2a 9911 are meant to replace carden 10496 in ZF without AC.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jan-2013.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 27-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 → (card‘𝐴) = (card‘𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | card1 9913* | A set has cardinality one iff it is a singleton. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ ((card‘𝐴) = 1o ↔ ∃𝑥 𝐴 = {𝑥}) | ||
Theorem | cardsn 9914 | A singleton has cardinality one. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (card‘{𝐴}) = 1o) | ||
Theorem | carddomi2 9915 | Two sets have the dominance relationship if their cardinalities have the subset relationship and one is numerable. See also carddom 10499, which uses AC. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jan-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) → ((card‘𝐴) ⊆ (card‘𝐵) → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | sdomsdomcardi 9916 | A set strictly dominates if its cardinal strictly dominates. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 13-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≺ (card‘𝐵) → 𝐴 ≺ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | cardlim 9917 | An infinite cardinal is a limit ordinal. Equivalent to Exercise 4 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 91. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 13-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (ω ⊆ (card‘𝐴) ↔ Lim (card‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | cardsdomelir 9918 | A cardinal strictly dominates its members. Equivalent to Proposition 10.37 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 93. This is half of the assertion cardsdomel 9919 and can be proven without the AC. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (card‘𝐵) → 𝐴 ≺ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | cardsdomel 9919 | A cardinal strictly dominates its members. Equivalent to Proposition 10.37 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 93. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Jan-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card) → (𝐴 ≺ 𝐵 ↔ 𝐴 ∈ (card‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | iscard 9920* | Two ways to express the property of being a cardinal number. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ ((card‘𝐴) = 𝐴 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ On ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥 ≺ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | iscard2 9921* | Two ways to express the property of being a cardinal number. Definition 8 of [Suppes] p. 225. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ ((card‘𝐴) = 𝐴 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ On ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ On (𝐴 ≈ 𝑥 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | carddom2 9922 | Two numerable sets have the dominance relationship iff their cardinalities have the subset relationship. See also carddom 10499, which uses AC. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jan-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card) → ((card‘𝐴) ⊆ (card‘𝐵) ↔ 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | harcard 9923 | The class of ordinal numbers dominated by a set is a cardinal number. Theorem 59 of [Suppes] p. 228. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-Jan-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (card‘(har‘𝐴)) = (har‘𝐴) | ||
Theorem | cardprclem 9924* | Lemma for cardprc 9925. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jan-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑥 ∣ (card‘𝑥) = 𝑥} ⇒ ⊢ ¬ 𝐴 ∈ V | ||
Theorem | cardprc 9925 | The class of all cardinal numbers is not a set (i.e. is a proper class). Theorem 19.8 of [Eisenberg] p. 310. In this proof (which does not use AC), we cannot use Cantor's construction canth3 10506 to ensure that there is always a cardinal larger than a given cardinal, but we can use Hartogs' construction hartogs 9489 to construct (effectively) (ℵ‘suc 𝐴) from (ℵ‘𝐴), which achieves the same thing. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ {𝑥 ∣ (card‘𝑥) = 𝑥} ∉ V | ||
Theorem | carduni 9926* | The union of a set of cardinals is a cardinal. Theorem 18.14 of [Monk1] p. 133. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (card‘𝑥) = 𝑥 → (card‘∪ 𝐴) = ∪ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | cardiun 9927* | The indexed union of a set of cardinals is a cardinal. (Contributed by NM, 3-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (card‘𝐵) = 𝐵 → (card‘∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵) = ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | cardennn 9928 | If 𝐴 is equinumerous to a natural number, then that number is its cardinal. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (card‘𝐴) = 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | cardsucinf 9929 | The cardinality of the successor of an infinite ordinal. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ ω ⊆ 𝐴) → (card‘suc 𝐴) = (card‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | cardsucnn 9930 | The cardinality of the successor of a finite ordinal (natural number). This theorem does not hold for infinite ordinals; see cardsucinf 9929. (Contributed by NM, 7-Nov-2008.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (card‘suc 𝐴) = suc (card‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | cardom 9931 | The set of natural numbers is a cardinal number. Theorem 18.11 of [Monk1] p. 133. (Contributed by NM, 28-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ (card‘ω) = ω | ||
Theorem | carden2 9932 | Two numerable sets are equinumerous iff their cardinal numbers are equal. Unlike carden 10496, the Axiom of Choice is not required. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card) → ((card‘𝐴) = (card‘𝐵) ↔ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | cardsdom2 9933 | A numerable set is strictly dominated by another iff their cardinalities are strictly ordered. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card) → ((card‘𝐴) ∈ (card‘𝐵) ↔ 𝐴 ≺ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | domtri2 9934 | Trichotomy of dominance for numerable sets (does not use AC). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card) → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ¬ 𝐵 ≺ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | nnsdomel 9935 | Strict dominance and elementhood are the same for finite ordinals. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ 𝐴 ≺ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | cardval2 9936* | An alternate version of the value of the cardinal number of a set. Compare cardval 10491. This theorem could be used to give a simpler definition of card in place of df-card 9884. It apparently does not occur in the literature. (Contributed by NM, 7-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ dom card → (card‘𝐴) = {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ 𝑥 ≺ 𝐴}) | ||
Theorem | isinffi 9937* | An infinite set contains subsets equinumerous to every finite set. Extension of isinf 9211 from finite ordinals to all finite sets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 8-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((¬ 𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐵 ∈ Fin) → ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐵–1-1→𝐴) | ||
Theorem | fidomtri 9938 | Trichotomy of dominance without AC when one set is finite. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 27-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ¬ 𝐵 ≺ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | fidomtri2 9939 | Trichotomy of dominance without AC when one set is finite. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ Fin) → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ¬ 𝐵 ≺ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | harsdom 9940 | The Hartogs number of a well-orderable set strictly dominates the set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ dom card → 𝐴 ≺ (har‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | onsdom 9941* | Any well-orderable set is strictly dominated by an ordinal number. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 22-Oct-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ dom card → ∃𝑥 ∈ On 𝐴 ≺ 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | harval2 9942* | An alternate expression for the Hartogs number of a well-orderable set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ dom card → (har‘𝐴) = ∩ {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ 𝐴 ≺ 𝑥}) | ||
Theorem | harsucnn 9943 | The next cardinal after a finite ordinal is the successor ordinal. (Contributed by RP, 5-Nov-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (har‘𝐴) = suc 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | cardmin2 9944* | The smallest ordinal that strictly dominates a set is a cardinal, if it exists. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥 ∈ On 𝐴 ≺ 𝑥 ↔ (card‘∩ {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ 𝐴 ≺ 𝑥}) = ∩ {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ 𝐴 ≺ 𝑥}) | ||
Theorem | pm54.43lem 9945* | In Theorem *54.43 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 360, the number 1 is defined as the collection of all sets with cardinality 1 (i.e. all singletons; see card1 9913), so that their 𝐴 ∈ 1 means, in our notation, 𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ (card‘𝑥) = 1o}. Here we show that this is equivalent to 𝐴 ≈ 1o so that we can use the latter more convenient notation in pm54.43 9946. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 1o ↔ 𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ (card‘𝑥) = 1o}) | ||
Theorem | pm54.43 9946 |
Theorem *54.43 of [WhiteheadRussell]
p. 360. "From this proposition it
will follow, when arithmetical addition has been defined, that
1+1=2."
See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Principia_Mathematica#Quotations.
This theorem states that two sets of cardinality 1 are disjoint iff
their union has cardinality 2.
Whitehead and Russell define 1 as the collection of all sets with cardinality 1 (i.e. all singletons; see card1 9913), so that their 𝐴 ∈ 1 means, in our notation, 𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ (card‘𝑥) = 1o} which is the same as 𝐴 ≈ 1o by pm54.43lem 9945. We do not have several of their earlier lemmas available (which would otherwise be unused by our different approach to arithmetic), so our proof is longer. (It is also longer because we must show every detail.) Theorem dju1p1e2 10118 shows the derivation of 1+1=2 for cardinal numbers from this theorem. (Contributed by NM, 4-Apr-2007.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≈ 1o ∧ 𝐵 ≈ 1o) → ((𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) = ∅ ↔ (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ≈ 2o)) | ||
Theorem | enpr2 9947 | An unordered pair with distinct elements is equinumerous to ordinal two. This is a closed-form version of enpr2d 9000. (Contributed by FL, 17-Aug-2008.) Avoid ax-pow 5325, ax-un 7677. (Revised by BTernaryTau, 30-Dec-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵) → {𝐴, 𝐵} ≈ 2o) | ||
Theorem | pr2nelemOLD 9948 | Obsolete version of enpr2 9947 as of 30-Dec-2024. (Contributed by FL, 17-Aug-2008.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵) → {𝐴, 𝐵} ≈ 2o) | ||
Theorem | pr2ne 9949 | If an unordered pair has two elements, then they are different. (Contributed by FL, 14-Feb-2010.) Avoid ax-pow 5325, ax-un 7677. (Revised by BTernaryTau, 30-Dec-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → ({𝐴, 𝐵} ≈ 2o ↔ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | pr2neOLD 9950 | Obsolete version of pr2ne 9949 as of 30-Dec-2024. (Contributed by FL, 14-Feb-2010.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → ({𝐴, 𝐵} ≈ 2o ↔ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | prdom2 9951 | An unordered pair has at most two elements. (Contributed by FL, 22-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → {𝐴, 𝐵} ≼ 2o) | ||
Theorem | en2eqpr 9952 | Building a set with two elements. (Contributed by FL, 11-Aug-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 10-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐶 ≈ 2o ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶) → (𝐴 ≠ 𝐵 → 𝐶 = {𝐴, 𝐵})) | ||
Theorem | en2eleq 9953 | Express a set of pair cardinality as the unordered pair of a given element and the other element. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝑃 ∧ 𝑃 ≈ 2o) → 𝑃 = {𝑋, ∪ (𝑃 ∖ {𝑋})}) | ||
Theorem | en2other2 9954 | Taking the other element twice in a pair gets back to the original element. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝑃 ∧ 𝑃 ≈ 2o) → ∪ (𝑃 ∖ {∪ (𝑃 ∖ {𝑋})}) = 𝑋) | ||
Theorem | dif1card 9955 | The cardinality of a nonempty finite set is one greater than the cardinality of the set with one element removed. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝐴) → (card‘𝐴) = suc (card‘(𝐴 ∖ {𝑋}))) | ||
Theorem | leweon 9956* | Lexicographical order is a well-ordering of On × On. Proposition 7.56(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 54. Note that unlike r0weon 9957, this order is not set-like, as the preimage of 〈1o, ∅〉 is the proper class ({∅} × On). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐿 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (On × On) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (On × On)) ∧ ((1st ‘𝑥) ∈ (1st ‘𝑦) ∨ ((1st ‘𝑥) = (1st ‘𝑦) ∧ (2nd ‘𝑥) ∈ (2nd ‘𝑦))))} ⇒ ⊢ 𝐿 We (On × On) | ||
Theorem | r0weon 9957* | A set-like well-ordering of the class of ordinal pairs. Proposition 7.58(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 54. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Mar-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐿 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (On × On) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (On × On)) ∧ ((1st ‘𝑥) ∈ (1st ‘𝑦) ∨ ((1st ‘𝑥) = (1st ‘𝑦) ∧ (2nd ‘𝑥) ∈ (2nd ‘𝑦))))} & ⊢ 𝑅 = {〈𝑧, 𝑤〉 ∣ ((𝑧 ∈ (On × On) ∧ 𝑤 ∈ (On × On)) ∧ (((1st ‘𝑧) ∪ (2nd ‘𝑧)) ∈ ((1st ‘𝑤) ∪ (2nd ‘𝑤)) ∨ (((1st ‘𝑧) ∪ (2nd ‘𝑧)) = ((1st ‘𝑤) ∪ (2nd ‘𝑤)) ∧ 𝑧𝐿𝑤)))} ⇒ ⊢ (𝑅 We (On × On) ∧ 𝑅 Se (On × On)) | ||
Theorem | infxpenlem 9958* | Lemma for infxpen 9959. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Mar-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐿 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (On × On) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (On × On)) ∧ ((1st ‘𝑥) ∈ (1st ‘𝑦) ∨ ((1st ‘𝑥) = (1st ‘𝑦) ∧ (2nd ‘𝑥) ∈ (2nd ‘𝑦))))} & ⊢ 𝑅 = {〈𝑧, 𝑤〉 ∣ ((𝑧 ∈ (On × On) ∧ 𝑤 ∈ (On × On)) ∧ (((1st ‘𝑧) ∪ (2nd ‘𝑧)) ∈ ((1st ‘𝑤) ∪ (2nd ‘𝑤)) ∨ (((1st ‘𝑧) ∪ (2nd ‘𝑧)) = ((1st ‘𝑤) ∪ (2nd ‘𝑤)) ∧ 𝑧𝐿𝑤)))} & ⊢ 𝑄 = (𝑅 ∩ ((𝑎 × 𝑎) × (𝑎 × 𝑎))) & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ((𝑎 ∈ On ∧ ∀𝑚 ∈ 𝑎 (ω ⊆ 𝑚 → (𝑚 × 𝑚) ≈ 𝑚)) ∧ (ω ⊆ 𝑎 ∧ ∀𝑚 ∈ 𝑎 𝑚 ≺ 𝑎))) & ⊢ 𝑀 = ((1st ‘𝑤) ∪ (2nd ‘𝑤)) & ⊢ 𝐽 = OrdIso(𝑄, (𝑎 × 𝑎)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ ω ⊆ 𝐴) → (𝐴 × 𝐴) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infxpen 9959 | Every infinite ordinal is equinumerous to its Cartesian square. Proposition 10.39 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 94, whose proof we follow closely. The key idea is to show that the relation 𝑅 is a well-ordering of (On × On) with the additional property that 𝑅-initial segments of (𝑥 × 𝑥) (where 𝑥 is a limit ordinal) are of cardinality at most 𝑥. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Mar-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ ω ⊆ 𝐴) → (𝐴 × 𝐴) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | xpomen 9960 | The Cartesian product of omega (the set of ordinal natural numbers) with itself is equinumerous to omega. Exercise 1 of [Enderton] p. 133. (Contributed by NM, 23-Jul-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ (ω × ω) ≈ ω | ||
Theorem | xpct 9961 | The cartesian product of two countable sets is countable. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 24-Sep-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ ω ∧ 𝐵 ≼ ω) → (𝐴 × 𝐵) ≼ ω) | ||
Theorem | infxpidm2 9962 | Every infinite well-orderable set is equinumerous to its Cartesian square. This theorem provides the basis for infinite cardinal arithmetic. Proposition 10.40 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 95. See also infxpidm 10507. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Mar-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴) → (𝐴 × 𝐴) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infxpenc 9963* | A canonical version of infxpen 9959, by a completely different approach (although it uses infxpen 9959 via xpomen 9960). Using Cantor's normal form, we can show that 𝐴 ↑o 𝐵 respects equinumerosity (oef1o 9643), so that all the steps of (ω↑𝑊) · (ω↑𝑊) ≈ ω↑(2𝑊) ≈ (ω↑2)↑𝑊 ≈ ω↑𝑊 can be verified using bijections to do the ordinal commutations. (The assumption on 𝑁 can be satisfied using cnfcom3c 9651.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2015.) (Revised by AV, 7-Jul-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ On) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ω ⊆ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑊 ∈ (On ∖ 1o)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:(ω ↑o 2o)–1-1-onto→ω) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹‘∅) = ∅) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁:𝐴–1-1-onto→(ω ↑o 𝑊)) & ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝑦 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ ((ω ↑o 2o) ↑m 𝑊) ∣ 𝑥 finSupp ∅} ↦ (𝐹 ∘ (𝑦 ∘ ◡( I ↾ 𝑊)))) & ⊢ 𝐻 = (((ω CNF 𝑊) ∘ 𝐾) ∘ ◡((ω ↑o 2o) CNF 𝑊)) & ⊢ 𝐿 = (𝑦 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ (ω ↑m (𝑊 ·o 2o)) ∣ 𝑥 finSupp ∅} ↦ (( I ↾ ω) ∘ (𝑦 ∘ ◡(𝑌 ∘ ◡𝑋)))) & ⊢ 𝑋 = (𝑧 ∈ 2o, 𝑤 ∈ 𝑊 ↦ ((𝑊 ·o 𝑧) +o 𝑤)) & ⊢ 𝑌 = (𝑧 ∈ 2o, 𝑤 ∈ 𝑊 ↦ ((2o ·o 𝑤) +o 𝑧)) & ⊢ 𝐽 = (((ω CNF (2o ·o 𝑊)) ∘ 𝐿) ∘ ◡(ω CNF (𝑊 ·o 2o))) & ⊢ 𝑍 = (𝑥 ∈ (ω ↑o 𝑊), 𝑦 ∈ (ω ↑o 𝑊) ↦ (((ω ↑o 𝑊) ·o 𝑥) +o 𝑦)) & ⊢ 𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 〈(𝑁‘𝑥), (𝑁‘𝑦)〉) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (◡𝑁 ∘ (((𝐻 ∘ 𝐽) ∘ 𝑍) ∘ 𝑇)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐺:(𝐴 × 𝐴)–1-1-onto→𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infxpenc2lem1 9964* | Lemma for infxpenc2 9967. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ On) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑏 ∈ 𝐴 (ω ⊆ 𝑏 → ∃𝑤 ∈ (On ∖ 1o)(𝑛‘𝑏):𝑏–1-1-onto→(ω ↑o 𝑤))) & ⊢ 𝑊 = (◡(𝑥 ∈ (On ∖ 1o) ↦ (ω ↑o 𝑥))‘ran (𝑛‘𝑏)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑏 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ ω ⊆ 𝑏)) → (𝑊 ∈ (On ∖ 1o) ∧ (𝑛‘𝑏):𝑏–1-1-onto→(ω ↑o 𝑊))) | ||
Theorem | infxpenc2lem2 9965* | Lemma for infxpenc2 9967. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2015.) (Revised by AV, 7-Jul-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ On) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑏 ∈ 𝐴 (ω ⊆ 𝑏 → ∃𝑤 ∈ (On ∖ 1o)(𝑛‘𝑏):𝑏–1-1-onto→(ω ↑o 𝑤))) & ⊢ 𝑊 = (◡(𝑥 ∈ (On ∖ 1o) ↦ (ω ↑o 𝑥))‘ran (𝑛‘𝑏)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:(ω ↑o 2o)–1-1-onto→ω) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹‘∅) = ∅) & ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝑦 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ ((ω ↑o 2o) ↑m 𝑊) ∣ 𝑥 finSupp ∅} ↦ (𝐹 ∘ (𝑦 ∘ ◡( I ↾ 𝑊)))) & ⊢ 𝐻 = (((ω CNF 𝑊) ∘ 𝐾) ∘ ◡((ω ↑o 2o) CNF 𝑊)) & ⊢ 𝐿 = (𝑦 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ (ω ↑m (𝑊 ·o 2o)) ∣ 𝑥 finSupp ∅} ↦ (( I ↾ ω) ∘ (𝑦 ∘ ◡(𝑌 ∘ ◡𝑋)))) & ⊢ 𝑋 = (𝑧 ∈ 2o, 𝑤 ∈ 𝑊 ↦ ((𝑊 ·o 𝑧) +o 𝑤)) & ⊢ 𝑌 = (𝑧 ∈ 2o, 𝑤 ∈ 𝑊 ↦ ((2o ·o 𝑤) +o 𝑧)) & ⊢ 𝐽 = (((ω CNF (2o ·o 𝑊)) ∘ 𝐿) ∘ ◡(ω CNF (𝑊 ·o 2o))) & ⊢ 𝑍 = (𝑥 ∈ (ω ↑o 𝑊), 𝑦 ∈ (ω ↑o 𝑊) ↦ (((ω ↑o 𝑊) ·o 𝑥) +o 𝑦)) & ⊢ 𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝑏, 𝑦 ∈ 𝑏 ↦ 〈((𝑛‘𝑏)‘𝑥), ((𝑛‘𝑏)‘𝑦)〉) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (◡(𝑛‘𝑏) ∘ (((𝐻 ∘ 𝐽) ∘ 𝑍) ∘ 𝑇)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑔∀𝑏 ∈ 𝐴 (ω ⊆ 𝑏 → (𝑔‘𝑏):(𝑏 × 𝑏)–1-1-onto→𝑏)) | ||
Theorem | infxpenc2lem3 9966* | Lemma for infxpenc2 9967. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2015.) (Revised by AV, 7-Jul-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ On) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑏 ∈ 𝐴 (ω ⊆ 𝑏 → ∃𝑤 ∈ (On ∖ 1o)(𝑛‘𝑏):𝑏–1-1-onto→(ω ↑o 𝑤))) & ⊢ 𝑊 = (◡(𝑥 ∈ (On ∖ 1o) ↦ (ω ↑o 𝑥))‘ran (𝑛‘𝑏)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:(ω ↑o 2o)–1-1-onto→ω) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹‘∅) = ∅) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑔∀𝑏 ∈ 𝐴 (ω ⊆ 𝑏 → (𝑔‘𝑏):(𝑏 × 𝑏)–1-1-onto→𝑏)) | ||
Theorem | infxpenc2 9967* | Existence form of infxpenc 9963. A "uniform" or "canonical" version of infxpen 9959, asserting the existence of a single function 𝑔 that simultaneously demonstrates product idempotence of all ordinals below a given bound. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → ∃𝑔∀𝑏 ∈ 𝐴 (ω ⊆ 𝑏 → (𝑔‘𝑏):(𝑏 × 𝑏)–1-1-onto→𝑏)) | ||
Theorem | iunmapdisj 9968* | The union ∪ 𝑛 ∈ 𝐶(𝐴 ↑m 𝑛) is a disjoint union. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) (Revised by NM, 16-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ ∃*𝑛 ∈ 𝐶 𝐵 ∈ (𝐴 ↑m 𝑛) | ||
Theorem | fseqenlem1 9969* | Lemma for fseqen 9972. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:(𝐴 × 𝐴)–1-1-onto→𝐴) & ⊢ 𝐺 = seqω((𝑛 ∈ V, 𝑓 ∈ V ↦ (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 ↑m suc 𝑛) ↦ ((𝑓‘(𝑥 ↾ 𝑛))𝐹(𝑥‘𝑛)))), {〈∅, 𝐵〉}) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) → (𝐺‘𝐶):(𝐴 ↑m 𝐶)–1-1→𝐴) | ||
Theorem | fseqenlem2 9970* | Lemma for fseqen 9972. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:(𝐴 × 𝐴)–1-1-onto→𝐴) & ⊢ 𝐺 = seqω((𝑛 ∈ V, 𝑓 ∈ V ↦ (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 ↑m suc 𝑛) ↦ ((𝑓‘(𝑥 ↾ 𝑛))𝐹(𝑥‘𝑛)))), {〈∅, 𝐵〉}) & ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝑦 ∈ ∪ 𝑘 ∈ ω (𝐴 ↑m 𝑘) ↦ 〈dom 𝑦, ((𝐺‘dom 𝑦)‘𝑦)〉) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐾:∪ 𝑘 ∈ ω (𝐴 ↑m 𝑘)–1-1→(ω × 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | fseqdom 9971* | One half of fseqen 9972. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (ω × 𝐴) ≼ ∪ 𝑛 ∈ ω (𝐴 ↑m 𝑛)) | ||
Theorem | fseqen 9972* | A set that is equinumerous to its Cartesian product is equinumerous to the set of finite sequences on it. (This can be proven more easily using some choice but this proof avoids it.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 × 𝐴) ≈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) → ∪ 𝑛 ∈ ω (𝐴 ↑m 𝑛) ≈ (ω × 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | infpwfidom 9973 | The collection of finite subsets of a set dominates the set. (We use the weaker sethood assumption (𝒫 𝐴 ∩ Fin) ∈ V because this theorem also implies that 𝐴 is a set if 𝒫 𝐴 ∩ Fin is.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝒫 𝐴 ∩ Fin) ∈ V → 𝐴 ≼ (𝒫 𝐴 ∩ Fin)) | ||
Theorem | dfac8alem 9974* | Lemma for dfac8a 9975. If the power set of a set has a choice function, then the set is numerable. (Contributed by NM, 10-Feb-1997.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 5-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = recs(𝐺) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑓 ∈ V ↦ (𝑔‘(𝐴 ∖ ran 𝑓))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 → (∃𝑔∀𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴(𝑦 ≠ ∅ → (𝑔‘𝑦) ∈ 𝑦) → 𝐴 ∈ dom card)) | ||
Theorem | dfac8a 9975* | Numeration theorem: every set with a choice function on its power set is numerable. With AC, this reduces to the statement that every set is numerable. Similar to Theorem 10.3 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 84. (Contributed by NM, 10-Feb-1997.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 5-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (∃ℎ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴(𝑦 ≠ ∅ → (ℎ‘𝑦) ∈ 𝑦) → 𝐴 ∈ dom card)) | ||
Theorem | dfac8b 9976* | The well-ordering theorem: every numerable set is well-orderable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Jan-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ dom card → ∃𝑥 𝑥 We 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dfac8clem 9977* | Lemma for dfac8c 9978. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑠 ∈ (𝐴 ∖ {∅}) ↦ (℩𝑎 ∈ 𝑠 ∀𝑏 ∈ 𝑠 ¬ 𝑏𝑟𝑎)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (∃𝑟 𝑟 We ∪ 𝐴 → ∃𝑓∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → (𝑓‘𝑧) ∈ 𝑧))) | ||
Theorem | dfac8c 9978* | If the union of a set is well-orderable, then the set has a choice function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (∃𝑟 𝑟 We ∪ 𝐴 → ∃𝑓∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → (𝑓‘𝑧) ∈ 𝑧))) | ||
Theorem | ac10ct 9979* | A proof of the well-ordering theorem weth 10440, an Axiom of Choice equivalent, restricted to sets dominated by some ordinal (in particular finite sets and countable sets), proven in ZF without AC. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (∃𝑦 ∈ On 𝐴 ≼ 𝑦 → ∃𝑥 𝑥 We 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ween 9980* | A set is numerable iff it can be well-ordered. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ dom card ↔ ∃𝑟 𝑟 We 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ac5num 9981* | A version of ac5b 10423 with the choice as a hypothesis. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((∪ 𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ¬ ∅ ∈ 𝐴) → ∃𝑓(𝑓:𝐴⟶∪ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑓‘𝑥) ∈ 𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | ondomen 9982 | If a set is dominated by an ordinal, then it is numerable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | numdom 9983 | A set dominated by a numerable set is numerable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | ssnum 9984 | A subset of a numerable set is numerable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | onssnum 9985 | All subsets of the ordinals are numerable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ On) → 𝐴 ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | indcardi 9986* | Indirect strong induction on the cardinality of a finite or numerable set. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ dom card) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑅 ≼ 𝑇 ∧ ∀𝑦(𝑆 ≺ 𝑅 → 𝜒)) → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝑅 = 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝑅 = 𝑇) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | acnrcl 9987 | Reverse closure for the choice set predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴 → 𝐴 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | acneq 9988 | Equality theorem for the choice set function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐶 → AC 𝐴 = AC 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | isacn 9989* | The property of being a choice set of length 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑓 ∈ ((𝒫 𝑋 ∖ {∅}) ↑m 𝐴)∃𝑔∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑔‘𝑥) ∈ (𝑓‘𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | acni 9990* | The property of being a choice set of length 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶(𝒫 𝑋 ∖ {∅})) → ∃𝑔∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑔‘𝑥) ∈ (𝐹‘𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | acni2 9991* | The property of being a choice set of length 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐵 ⊆ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅)) → ∃𝑔(𝑔:𝐴⟶𝑋 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑔‘𝑥) ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | acni3 9992* | The property of being a choice set of length 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑦 = (𝑔‘𝑥) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 𝜑) → ∃𝑔(𝑔:𝐴⟶𝑋 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | acnlem 9993* | Construct a mapping satisfying the consequent of isacn 9989. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ (𝑓‘𝑥)) → ∃𝑔∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑔‘𝑥) ∈ (𝑓‘𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | numacn 9994 | A well-orderable set has choice sequences of every length. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝑋 ∈ dom card → 𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | finacn 9995 | Every set has finite choice sequences. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Fin → AC 𝐴 = V) | ||
Theorem | acndom 9996 | A set with long choice sequences also has shorter choice sequences, where "shorter" here means the new index set is dominated by the old index set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 → (𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐵 → 𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | acnnum 9997 | A set 𝑋 which has choice sequences on it of length 𝒫 𝑋 is well-orderable (and hence has choice sequences of every length). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ AC 𝒫 𝑋 ↔ 𝑋 ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | acnen 9998 | The class of choice sets of length 𝐴 is a cardinal invariant. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 → AC 𝐴 = AC 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | acndom2 9999 | A set smaller than one with choice sequences of length 𝐴 also has choice sequences of length 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ≼ 𝑌 → (𝑌 ∈ AC 𝐴 → 𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | acnen2 10000 | The class of sets with choice sequences of length 𝐴 is a cardinal invariant. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ≈ 𝑌 → (𝑋 ∈ AC 𝐴 ↔ 𝑌 ∈ AC 𝐴)) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |